<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<h1>THE DISCOVERY<br/> OF THE FUTURE</h1>
<p class="author"><span class="title1">BY</span><br/>
H. G. WELLS</p>
<p></p>
<p class="title3">THE DISCOVERY OF THE FUTURE<SPAN name="FNanchor_1"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_1" class="fnanchor">[1]</SPAN><br/>
<span class="author1">By H. G. Wells</span></p>
<p>It will lead into my subject most conveniently to contrast and separate
two divergent types of mind, types which are to be distinguished chiefly
by their attitude toward time, and more particularly by the relative importance
they attach and the relative amount of thought they give to the future.</p>
<p>The first of these two types of mind, and it is, I think, the predominant
type, the type of the majority of living people, is that which seems scarcely
to think of the future at all, which regards it as a sort of blank non-existence
upon which the advancing present
will presently write events. The second type, which is, I think, a more
modern and much less abundant type of mind, thinks constantly and by preference
of things to come, and of present things mainly in relation to the results
that must arise from them. The former type of mind, when one gets it in
its purity, is retrospective in habit, and it interprets the things of
the present, and gives value to this and denies it to that, entirely with
relation to the past. The latter type of mind is constructive in habit,
it interprets the things of the present and gives value to this or that,
entirely in relation to things designed or foreseen.</p>
<p>While from that former point of view our life is simply to reap the consequences
of the past, from this our life is to prepare the future. The former type
one might speak of as the legal or submissive type of mind, because the
business, the practice, and the training of a lawyer dispose him toward
it; he of all men must constantly refer to the law made, the right established,
the precedent set, and consistently ignore or condemn the thing that is
only seeking to establish itself. The latter type of mind I might for contrast
call the legislative, creative, organizing, or masterful type, because
it is perpetually attacking and altering the established order of things,
perpetually falling away from respect for what the past has given us. It
sees the world as one great workshop, and the present is no more than material
for the future, for the thing that is yet destined to be. It is in the
active mood of thought, while the former is in the passive; it is the mind
of youth, it is the mind more manifest among the western nations, while
the former is the mind of age, the mind of the oriental.</p>
<p>Things have been, says the legal mind, and so we are here. The creative
mind says we are here because things have yet to be.</p>
<p>Now I do not wish to suggest that the great
mass of people belong to either of these two types. Indeed, I speak of
them as two distinct and distinguishable types mainly for convenience and
in order to accentuate their distinction. There are probably very few people
who brood constantly upon the past without any thought of the future at
all, and there are probably scarcely any who live and think consistently
in relation to the future. The great mass of people occupy an intermediate
position between these extremes, they pass daily and hourly from the passive
mood to the active, they see this thing in relation to its associations
and that thing in relation to its consequences, and they do not even suspect
that they are using two distinct methods in their minds.</p>
<p>But for all that they are distinct methods, the method of reference to
the past and the method of reference to the future, and their mingling
in many of our minds no more abolishes their difference than the existence
of piebald horses proves that white is black.</p>
<p>I believe that it is not sufficiently recognized just how different in
their consequences these two methods are, and just where their difference
and where the failure to appreciate their difference takes one. This present
time is a period of quite extraordinary uncertainty and indecision upon
endless questions—moral questions, æsthetic questions, religious and political
questions—upon which we should all of us be happier to feel assured and
settled; and a very large amount of this floating uncertainty about these
important matters is due to the fact that with most of us these two insufficiently
distinguished ways of looking at things are not only present together,
but in actual conflict in our minds, in unsuspected conflict; we pass from
one to the other heedlessly without any clear recognition of the fundamental
difference in conclusions that exists between the two, and we
do this with disastrous results to our confidence and to our consistency
in dealing with all sorts of things.</p>
<p>But before pointing out how divergent these two types or habits of mind
really are, it is necessary to meet a possible objection to what has been
said. I may put that objection in this form: Is not this distinction between
a type of mind that thinks of the past and a type of mind that thinks of
the future a sort of hair-splitting, almost like distinguishing between
people who have left hands and people who have right? Everybody believes
that the present is entirely determined by the past, you say; but then
everybody believes also that the present determines the future. Are we
simply separating and contrasting two sides of everybody’s opinion? To
which one replies that we are not discussing what we know and believe about
the relations of past, present, and future, or of the relation of cause
and effect to each other in time. We
all know the present depends for its causes on the past, and the future
depends for its causes upon the present. But this discussion concerns the
way in which we approach things upon this common ground of knowledge and
belief. We may all know there is an east and a west, but if some of us
always approach and look at things from the west, if some of us always
approach and look at things from the east, and if others again wander about
with a pretty disregard of direction, looking at things as chance determines,
some of us will get to a westward conclusion of this journey, and some
of us will get to an eastward conclusion, and some of us will get to no
definite conclusion at all about all sorts of important matters. And yet
those who are travelling east, and those who are travelling west, and those
who are wandering haphazard, may be all upon the same ground of belief
and statement and amid the same assembly of proven facts. Precisely the
same thing, divergence of
result, will happen if you always approach things from the point of view
of their causes, or if you approach them always with a view to their probable
effects. And in several very important groups of human affairs it is possible
to show quite clearly just how widely apart the two methods, pursued each
in its purity, take those who follow them.</p>
<p>I suppose that three hundred years ago all people who thought at all about
moral questions, about questions of Right and Wrong, deduced their rules
of conduct absolutely and unreservedly from the past, from some dogmatic
injunction, some finally settled decree. The great mass of people do so
to-day. It is written, they say. “Thou shalt not steal,” for example—that
is the sole, complete, sufficient reason why you should not steal, and
even to-day there is a strong aversion to admit that there is any relation
between the actual consequences of acts and the imperatives of right
and wrong. Our lives are to reap the fruits of determinate things, and
it is still a fundamental presumption of the established morality that
one must do right though the heavens fall. But there are people coming
into this world who would refuse to call it Right if it brought the heavens
about our heads, however authoritative its sources and sanctions, and this
new disposition is, I believe, a growing one. I suppose in all ages people
in a timid, hesitating, guilty way have tempered the austerity of a dogmatic
moral code by small infractions to secure obviously kindly ends, but it
was, I am told, the Jesuits who first deliberately sought to qualify the
moral interpretation of acts by a consideration of their results. To-day
there are few people who have not more or less clearly discovered the future
as a more or less important factor in moral considerations. To-day there
is a certain small proportion of people who frankly regard morality as
a means to an end,
as an overriding of immediate and personal considerations out of regard
to something to be attained in the future, and who break away altogether
from the idea of a code dogmatically established forever.</p>
<p>Most of us are not so definite as that, but most of us are deeply tinged
with the spirit of compromise between the past and the future; we profess
an unbounded allegiance to the prescriptions of the past, and we practise
a general observance of its injunctions, but we qualify to a vague, variable
extent with considerations of expediency. We hold, for example, that we
must respect our promises. But suppose we find unexpectedly that for one
of us to keep a promise, which has been sealed and sworn in the most sacred
fashion, must lead to the great suffering of some other human being, must
lead, in fact, to practical evil? Would a man do right or wrong if he broke
such a promise? The practical decision most modern people would make would
be to break the promise. Most would say that they did evil to avoid a greater
evil. But suppose it was not such very great suffering we were going to
inflict, but only some suffering? And suppose it was a rather important
promise? With most of us it would then come to be a matter of weighing
the promise, the thing of the past, against this unexpected bad consequence,
the thing of the future. And the smaller the overplus of evil consequences
the more most of us would vacillate. But neither of the two types of mind
we are contrasting would vacillate at all. The legal type of mind would
obey the past unhesitatingly, the creative would unhesitatingly sacrifice
it to the future. The legal mind would say, “they who break the law at
any point break it altogether,” while the creative mind would say, “let
the dead past bury its dead.”</p>
<p>It is convenient to take my illustration from the sphere of promises,
but it is in the realm
of sexual morality that the two methods are most acutely in conflict.</p>
<p>And I would like to suggest that until you have definitely determined
either to obey the real or imaginary imperatives of the past, or to set
yourself toward the demands of some ideal of the future, until you have
made up your mind to adhere to one or other of these two types of mental
action in these matters, you are not even within hope of a sustained consistency
in the thought that underlies your acts, that in every issue of principle
that comes upon you, you will be entirely at the mercy of the intellectual
mood that happens to be ascendent at that particular moment in your mind.</p>
<p>In the sphere of public affairs also these two ways of looking at things
work out into equally divergent and incompatible consequences. The legal
mind insists upon treaties, constitutions, legitimacies, and charters;
the legislative incessantly assails these.
Whenever some period of stress sets in, some great conflict between institutions
and the forces in things, there comes a sorting out of these two types
of mind. The legal mind becomes glorified and transfigured in the form
of hopeless loyalty, the creative mind inspires revolutions and reconstructions.
And particularly is this difference of attitude accentuated in the disputes
that arise out of wars. In most modern wars there is no doubt quite traceable
on one side or the other a distinct creative idea, a distinct regard for
some future consequence; but the main dispute even in most modern wars
and the sole dispute in most mediæval wars will be found to be a reference,
not to the future, but to the past; to turn upon a question of fact and
right. The wars of Plantagenet and Lancastrian England with France, for
example, were based entirely upon a dummy claim, supported by obscure legal
arguments, upon the crown of France. And
the arguments that centered about the late war in South Africa ignored
any ideal of a great united South African state almost entirely, and quibbled
this way and that about who began the fighting and what was or was not
written in some obscure revision of a treaty a score of years ago. Yet
beneath the legal issues the broad creative idea has been apparent in the
public mind during this war. It will be found more or less definitely formulated
beneath almost all the great wars of the past century, and a comparison
of the wars of the nineteenth century with the wars of the middle ages
will show, I think, that in this field also there has been a discovery
of the future, an increasing disposition to shift the reference and values
from things accomplished to things to come.</p>
<p>Yet though foresight creeps into our politics and a reference to consequence
into our morality, it is still the past that dominates our lives. But why?
Why are we so bound
to it? It is into the future we go, to-morrow is the eventful thing for
us. There lies all that remains to be felt by us and our children and all
those that are dear to us. Yet we marshal and order men into classes entirely
with regard to the past; we draw shame and honor out of the past; against
the rights of property, the vested interests, the agreements and establishments
of the past the future has no rights. Literature is for the most part history
or history at one remove, and what is culture but a mold of interpretation
into which new things are thrust, a collection of standards, a sort of
bed of King Og, to which all new expressions must be lopped or stretched?
Our conveniences, like our thoughts, are all retrospective. We travel on
roads so narrow that they suffocate our traffic; we live in uncomfortable,
inconvenient, life-wasting houses out of a love of familiar shapes and
familiar customs and a dread of strangeness; all our public affairs are
cramped by local boundaries impossibly restricted and small. Our clothing,
our habits of speech, our spelling, our weights and measures, our coinage,
our religious and political theories, all witness to the binding power
of the past upon our minds. Yet we do not serve the past as the Chinese
have done. There are degrees. We do not worship our ancestors or prescribe
a rigid local costume; we dare to enlarge our stock of knowledge, and we
qualify the classics with occasional adventures into original thought.
Compared with the Chinese we are distinctly aware of the future. But compared
with what we might be, the past is all our world.</p>
<p>The reason why the retrospective habit, the legal habit, is so dominant,
and always has been so predominant, is of course a perfectly obvious one.
We follow a fundamental human principle and take what we can get. All people
believe the past is certain, defined, and knowable, and only a few
people believe that it is possible to know anything about the future. Man
has acquired the habit of going to the past because it was the line of
least resistance for his mind. While a certain variable portion of the
past is serviceable matter for knowledge in the case of everyone, the future
is, to a mind without an imagination trained in scientific habits of thought,
non-existent. All our minds are made of memories. In our memories each
of us has something that without any special training whatever will go
back into the past and grip firmly and convincingly all sorts of workable
facts, sometimes more convincingly than firmly. But the imagination, unless
it is strengthened by a very sound training in the laws of causation, wanders
like a lost child in the blankness of things to come and returns empty.</p>
<p>Many people believe, therefore, that there can be no sort of certainty
about the future. You can know no more about the future,
I was recently assured by a friend, than you can know which way a kitten
will jump next. And to all who hold that view, who regard the future as
a perpetual source of convulsive surprises, as an impenetrable, incurable,
perpetual blankness, it is right and reasonable to derive such values as
it is necessary to attach to things from the events that have certainly
happened with regard to them. It is our ignorance of the future and our
persuasion that that ignorance is absolutely incurable that alone gives
the past its enormous predominance in our thoughts. But through the ages,
the long unbroken succession of fortune-tellers—and they flourish still—witnesses
to the perpetually smoldering feeling that after all there may be a better
sort of knowledge—a more serviceable sort of knowledge than that we now
possess.</p>
<p>On the whole there is something sympathetic for the dupe of the fortune-teller
in the spirit of modern science; it is one of the
persuasions that come into one’s mind, as one assimilates the broad conception
of science, that the adequacy of causation is universal; that in absolute
fact—if not in that little bubble of relative fact which constitutes the
individual life—in absolute fact the future is just as fixed and determinate,
just as settled and inevitable, just as possible a matter of knowledge
as the past. Our personal memory gives us an impression of the superior
reality and trustworthiness of things in the past, as of things that have
finally committed themselves and said their say, but the more clearly we
master the leading conceptions of science the better we understand that
this impression is one of the results of the peculiar conditions of our
lives, and not an absolute truth. The man of science comes to believe at
last that the events of the year A.D. 4000 are as fixed, settled, and unchangeable
as the events of the year 1600. Only about the latter he has some material
for belief and about the former practically none.</p>
<p>And the question arises how far this absolute ignorance of the future
is a fixed and necessary condition of human life, and how far some application
of intellectual methods may not attenuate even if it does not absolutely
set aside the veil between ourselves and things to come. And I am venturing
to suggest to you that along certain lines and with certain qualifications
and limitations a working knowledge of things in the future is a possible
and practicable thing. And in order to support this suggestion I would
call your attention to certain facts about our knowledge of the past, and
more particularly I would insist upon this, that about the past our range
of absolute certainty is very limited indeed. About the past I would suggest
we are inclined to overestimate our certainty, just as I think we are inclined
to underestimate the certainties of the future. And such a knowledge of
the past as we have
is not all of the same sort or derived from the same sources.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />