<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<h1> SYMPOSIUM </h1>
<h2> By Plato </h2>
<h3> Translated by Benjamin Jowett </h3>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0002" id="link2H_4_0002"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> SYMPOSIUM </h2>
<p>Concerning the things about which you ask to be informed I believe that I
am not ill-prepared with an answer. For the day before yesterday I was
coming from my own home at Phalerum to the city, and one of my
acquaintance, who had caught a sight of me from behind, calling out
playfully in the distance, said: Apollodorus, O thou Phalerian (Probably a
play of words on (Greek), 'bald-headed.') man, halt! So I did as I was
bid; and then he said, I was looking for you, Apollodorus, only just now,
that I might ask you about the speeches in praise of love, which were
delivered by Socrates, Alcibiades, and others, at Agathon's supper.
Phoenix, the son of Philip, told another person who told me of them; his
narrative was very indistinct, but he said that you knew, and I wish that
you would give me an account of them. Who, if not you, should be the
reporter of the words of your friend? And first tell me, he said, were you
present at this meeting?</p>
<p>Your informant, Glaucon, I said, must have been very indistinct indeed, if
you imagine that the occasion was recent; or that I could have been of the
party.</p>
<p>Why, yes, he replied, I thought so.</p>
<p>Impossible: I said. Are you ignorant that for many years Agathon has not
resided at Athens; and not three have elapsed since I became acquainted
with Socrates, and have made it my daily business to know all that he says
and does. There was a time when I was running about the world, fancying
myself to be well employed, but I was really a most wretched being, no
better than you are now. I thought that I ought to do anything rather than
be a philosopher.</p>
<p>Well, he said, jesting apart, tell me when the meeting occurred.</p>
<p>In our boyhood, I replied, when Agathon won the prize with his first
tragedy, on the day after that on which he and his chorus offered the
sacrifice of victory.</p>
<p>Then it must have been a long while ago, he said; and who told you—did
Socrates?</p>
<p>No indeed, I replied, but the same person who told Phoenix;—he was a
little fellow, who never wore any shoes, Aristodemus, of the deme of
Cydathenaeum. He had been at Agathon's feast; and I think that in those
days there was no one who was a more devoted admirer of Socrates.
Moreover, I have asked Socrates about the truth of some parts of his
narrative, and he confirmed them. Then, said Glaucon, let us have the tale
over again; is not the road to Athens just made for conversation? And so
we walked, and talked of the discourses on love; and therefore, as I said
at first, I am not ill-prepared to comply with your request, and will have
another rehearsal of them if you like. For to speak or to hear others
speak of philosophy always gives me the greatest pleasure, to say nothing
of the profit. But when I hear another strain, especially that of you rich
men and traders, such conversation displeases me; and I pity you who are
my companions, because you think that you are doing something when in
reality you are doing nothing. And I dare say that you pity me in return,
whom you regard as an unhappy creature, and very probably you are right.
But I certainly know of you what you only think of me—there is the
difference.</p>
<p>COMPANION: I see, Apollodorus, that you are just the same—always
speaking evil of yourself, and of others; and I do believe that you pity
all mankind, with the exception of Socrates, yourself first of all, true
in this to your old name, which, however deserved, I know not how you
acquired, of Apollodorus the madman; for you are always raging against
yourself and everybody but Socrates.</p>
<p>APOLLODORUS: Yes, friend, and the reason why I am said to be mad, and out
of my wits, is just because I have these notions of myself and you; no
other evidence is required.</p>
<p>COMPANION: No more of that, Apollodorus; but let me renew my request that
you would repeat the conversation.</p>
<p>APOLLODORUS: Well, the tale of love was on this wise:—But perhaps I
had better begin at the beginning, and endeavour to give you the exact
words of Aristodemus:</p>
<p>He said that he met Socrates fresh from the bath and sandalled; and as the
sight of the sandals was unusual, he asked him whither he was going that
he had been converted into such a beau:—</p>
<p>To a banquet at Agathon's, he replied, whose invitation to his sacrifice
of victory I refused yesterday, fearing a crowd, but promising that I
would come to-day instead; and so I have put on my finery, because he is
such a fine man. What say you to going with me unasked?</p>
<p>I will do as you bid me, I replied.</p>
<p>Follow then, he said, and let us demolish the proverb:—</p>
<p>'To the feasts of inferior men the good unbidden go;'</p>
<p>instead of which our proverb will run:—</p>
<p>'To the feasts of the good the good unbidden go;'</p>
<p>and this alteration may be supported by the authority of Homer himself,
who not only demolishes but literally outrages the proverb. For, after
picturing Agamemnon as the most valiant of men, he makes Menelaus, who is
but a fainthearted warrior, come unbidden (Iliad) to the banquet of
Agamemnon, who is feasting and offering sacrifices, not the better to the
worse, but the worse to the better.</p>
<p>I rather fear, Socrates, said Aristodemus, lest this may still be my case;
and that, like Menelaus in Homer, I shall be the inferior person, who</p>
<p>'To the feasts of the wise unbidden goes.'</p>
<p>But I shall say that I was bidden of you, and then you will have to make
an excuse.</p>
<p>'Two going together,'</p>
<p>he replied, in Homeric fashion, one or other of them may invent an excuse
by the way (Iliad).</p>
<p>This was the style of their conversation as they went along. Socrates
dropped behind in a fit of abstraction, and desired Aristodemus, who was
waiting, to go on before him. When he reached the house of Agathon he
found the doors wide open, and a comical thing happened. A servant coming
out met him, and led him at once into the banqueting-hall in which the
guests were reclining, for the banquet was about to begin. Welcome,
Aristodemus, said Agathon, as soon as he appeared—you are just in
time to sup with us; if you come on any other matter put it off, and make
one of us, as I was looking for you yesterday and meant to have asked you,
if I could have found you. But what have you done with Socrates?</p>
<p>I turned round, but Socrates was nowhere to be seen; and I had to explain
that he had been with me a moment before, and that I came by his
invitation to the supper.</p>
<p>You were quite right in coming, said Agathon; but where is he himself?</p>
<p>He was behind me just now, as I entered, he said, and I cannot think what
has become of him.</p>
<p>Go and look for him, boy, said Agathon, and bring him in; and do you,
Aristodemus, meanwhile take the place by Eryximachus.</p>
<p>The servant then assisted him to wash, and he lay down, and presently
another servant came in and reported that our friend Socrates had retired
into the portico of the neighbouring house. 'There he is fixed,' said he,
'and when I call to him he will not stir.'</p>
<p>How strange, said Agathon; then you must call him again, and keep calling
him.</p>
<p>Let him alone, said my informant; he has a way of stopping anywhere and
losing himself without any reason. I believe that he will soon appear; do
not therefore disturb him.</p>
<p>Well, if you think so, I will leave him, said Agathon. And then, turning
to the servants, he added, 'Let us have supper without waiting for him.
Serve up whatever you please, for there is no one to give you orders;
hitherto I have never left you to yourselves. But on this occasion imagine
that you are our hosts, and that I and the company are your guests; treat
us well, and then we shall commend you.' After this, supper was served,
but still no Socrates; and during the meal Agathon several times expressed
a wish to send for him, but Aristodemus objected; and at last when the
feast was about half over—for the fit, as usual, was not of long
duration—Socrates entered. Agathon, who was reclining alone at the
end of the table, begged that he would take the place next to him; that 'I
may touch you,' he said, 'and have the benefit of that wise thought which
came into your mind in the portico, and is now in your possession; for I
am certain that you would not have come away until you had found what you
sought.'</p>
<p>How I wish, said Socrates, taking his place as he was desired, that wisdom
could be infused by touch, out of the fuller into the emptier man, as
water runs through wool out of a fuller cup into an emptier one; if that
were so, how greatly should I value the privilege of reclining at your
side! For you would have filled me full with a stream of wisdom plenteous
and fair; whereas my own is of a very mean and questionable sort, no
better than a dream. But yours is bright and full of promise, and was
manifested forth in all the splendour of youth the day before yesterday,
in the presence of more than thirty thousand Hellenes.</p>
<p>You are mocking, Socrates, said Agathon, and ere long you and I will have
to determine who bears off the palm of wisdom—of this Dionysus shall
be the judge; but at present you are better occupied with supper.</p>
<p>Socrates took his place on the couch, and supped with the rest; and then
libations were offered, and after a hymn had been sung to the god, and
there had been the usual ceremonies, they were about to commence drinking,
when Pausanias said, And now, my friends, how can we drink with least
injury to ourselves? I can assure you that I feel severely the effect of
yesterday's potations, and must have time to recover; and I suspect that
most of you are in the same predicament, for you were of the party
yesterday. Consider then: How can the drinking be made easiest?</p>
<p>I entirely agree, said Aristophanes, that we should, by all means, avoid
hard drinking, for I was myself one of those who were yesterday drowned in
drink.</p>
<p>I think that you are right, said Eryximachus, the son of Acumenus; but I
should still like to hear one other person speak: Is Agathon able to drink
hard?</p>
<p>I am not equal to it, said Agathon.</p>
<p>Then, said Eryximachus, the weak heads like myself, Aristodemus, Phaedrus,
and others who never can drink, are fortunate in finding that the stronger
ones are not in a drinking mood. (I do not include Socrates, who is able
either to drink or to abstain, and will not mind, whichever we do.) Well,
as of none of the company seem disposed to drink much, I may be forgiven
for saying, as a physician, that drinking deep is a bad practice, which I
never follow, if I can help, and certainly do not recommend to another,
least of all to any one who still feels the effects of yesterday's
carouse.</p>
<p>I always do what you advise, and especially what you prescribe as a
physician, rejoined Phaedrus the Myrrhinusian, and the rest of the
company, if they are wise, will do the same.</p>
<p>It was agreed that drinking was not to be the order of the day, but that
they were all to drink only so much as they pleased.</p>
<p>Then, said Eryximachus, as you are all agreed that drinking is to be
voluntary, and that there is to be no compulsion, I move, in the next
place, that the flute-girl, who has just made her appearance, be told to
go away and play to herself, or, if she likes, to the women who are within
(compare Prot.). To-day let us have conversation instead; and, if you will
allow me, I will tell you what sort of conversation. This proposal having
been accepted, Eryximachus proceeded as follows:—</p>
<p>I will begin, he said, after the manner of Melanippe in Euripides,</p>
<p>'Not mine the word'</p>
<p>which I am about to speak, but that of Phaedrus. For often he says to me
in an indignant tone:—'What a strange thing it is, Eryximachus,
that, whereas other gods have poems and hymns made in their honour, the
great and glorious god, Love, has no encomiast among all the poets who are
so many. There are the worthy sophists too—the excellent Prodicus
for example, who have descanted in prose on the virtues of Heracles and
other heroes; and, what is still more extraordinary, I have met with a
philosophical work in which the utility of salt has been made the theme of
an eloquent discourse; and many other like things have had a like honour
bestowed upon them. And only to think that there should have been an eager
interest created about them, and yet that to this day no one has ever
dared worthily to hymn Love's praises! So entirely has this great deity
been neglected.' Now in this Phaedrus seems to me to be quite right, and
therefore I want to offer him a contribution; also I think that at the
present moment we who are here assembled cannot do better than honour the
god Love. If you agree with me, there will be no lack of conversation; for
I mean to propose that each of us in turn, going from left to right, shall
make a speech in honour of Love. Let him give us the best which he can;
and Phaedrus, because he is sitting first on the left hand, and because he
is the father of the thought, shall begin.</p>
<p>No one will vote against you, Eryximachus, said Socrates. How can I oppose
your motion, who profess to understand nothing but matters of love; nor, I
presume, will Agathon and Pausanias; and there can be no doubt of
Aristophanes, whose whole concern is with Dionysus and Aphrodite; nor will
any one disagree of those whom I see around me. The proposal, as I am
aware, may seem rather hard upon us whose place is last; but we shall be
contented if we hear some good speeches first. Let Phaedrus begin the
praise of Love, and good luck to him. All the company expressed their
assent, and desired him to do as Socrates bade him.</p>
<p>Aristodemus did not recollect all that was said, nor do I recollect all
that he related to me; but I will tell you what I thought most worthy of
remembrance, and what the chief speakers said.</p>
<p>Phaedrus began by affirming that Love is a mighty god, and wonderful among
gods and men, but especially wonderful in his birth. For he is the eldest
of the gods, which is an honour to him; and a proof of his claim to this
honour is, that of his parents there is no memorial; neither poet nor
prose-writer has ever affirmed that he had any. As Hesiod says:—</p>
<p>'First Chaos came, and then broad-bosomed Earth, The everlasting seat of
all that is, And Love.'</p>
<p>In other words, after Chaos, the Earth and Love, these two, came into
being. Also Parmenides sings of Generation:</p>
<p>'First in the train of gods, he fashioned Love.'</p>
<p>And Acusilaus agrees with Hesiod. Thus numerous are the witnesses who
acknowledge Love to be the eldest of the gods. And not only is he the
eldest, he is also the source of the greatest benefits to us. For I know
not any greater blessing to a young man who is beginning life than a
virtuous lover, or to the lover than a beloved youth. For the principle
which ought to be the guide of men who would nobly live—that
principle, I say, neither kindred, nor honour, nor wealth, nor any other
motive is able to implant so well as love. Of what am I speaking? Of the
sense of honour and dishonour, without which neither states nor
individuals ever do any good or great work. And I say that a lover who is
detected in doing any dishonourable act, or submitting through cowardice
when any dishonour is done to him by another, will be more pained at being
detected by his beloved than at being seen by his father, or by his
companions, or by any one else. The beloved too, when he is found in any
disgraceful situation, has the same feeling about his lover. And if there
were only some way of contriving that a state or an army should be made up
of lovers and their loves (compare Rep.), they would be the very best
governors of their own city, abstaining from all dishonour, and emulating
one another in honour; and when fighting at each other's side, although a
mere handful, they would overcome the world. For what lover would not
choose rather to be seen by all mankind than by his beloved, either when
abandoning his post or throwing away his arms? He would be ready to die a
thousand deaths rather than endure this. Or who would desert his beloved
or fail him in the hour of danger? The veriest coward would become an
inspired hero, equal to the bravest, at such a time; Love would inspire
him. That courage which, as Homer says, the god breathes into the souls of
some heroes, Love of his own nature infuses into the lover.</p>
<p>Love will make men dare to die for their beloved—love alone; and
women as well as men. Of this, Alcestis, the daughter of Pelias, is a
monument to all Hellas; for she was willing to lay down her life on behalf
of her husband, when no one else would, although he had a father and
mother; but the tenderness of her love so far exceeded theirs, that she
made them seem to be strangers in blood to their own son, and in name only
related to him; and so noble did this action of hers appear to the gods,
as well as to men, that among the many who have done virtuously she is one
of the very few to whom, in admiration of her noble action, they have
granted the privilege of returning alive to earth; such exceeding honour
is paid by the gods to the devotion and virtue of love. But Orpheus, the
son of Oeagrus, the harper, they sent empty away, and presented to him an
apparition only of her whom he sought, but herself they would not give up,
because he showed no spirit; he was only a harp-player, and did not dare
like Alcestis to die for love, but was contriving how he might enter Hades
alive; moreover, they afterwards caused him to suffer death at the hands
of women, as the punishment of his cowardliness. Very different was the
reward of the true love of Achilles towards his lover Patroclus—his
lover and not his love (the notion that Patroclus was the beloved one is a
foolish error into which Aeschylus has fallen, for Achilles was surely the
fairer of the two, fairer also than all the other heroes; and, as Homer
informs us, he was still beardless, and younger far). And greatly as the
gods honour the virtue of love, still the return of love on the part of
the beloved to the lover is more admired and valued and rewarded by them,
for the lover is more divine; because he is inspired by God. Now Achilles
was quite aware, for he had been told by his mother, that he might avoid
death and return home, and live to a good old age, if he abstained from
slaying Hector. Nevertheless he gave his life to revenge his friend, and
dared to die, not only in his defence, but after he was dead. Wherefore
the gods honoured him even above Alcestis, and sent him to the Islands of
the Blest. These are my reasons for affirming that Love is the eldest and
noblest and mightiest of the gods; and the chiefest author and giver of
virtue in life, and of happiness after death.</p>
<p>This, or something like this, was the speech of Phaedrus; and some other
speeches followed which Aristodemus did not remember; the next which he
repeated was that of Pausanias. Phaedrus, he said, the argument has not
been set before us, I think, quite in the right form;—we should not
be called upon to praise Love in such an indiscriminate manner. If there
were only one Love, then what you said would be well enough; but since
there are more Loves than one,—should have begun by determining
which of them was to be the theme of our praises. I will amend this
defect; and first of all I will tell you which Love is deserving of
praise, and then try to hymn the praiseworthy one in a manner worthy of
him. For we all know that Love is inseparable from Aphrodite, and if there
were only one Aphrodite there would be only one Love; but as there are two
goddesses there must be two Loves. And am I not right in asserting that
there are two goddesses? The elder one, having no mother, who is called
the heavenly Aphrodite—she is the daughter of Uranus; the younger,
who is the daughter of Zeus and Dione—her we call common; and the
Love who is her fellow-worker is rightly named common, as the other love
is called heavenly. All the gods ought to have praise given to them, but
not without distinction of their natures; and therefore I must try to
distinguish the characters of the two Loves. Now actions vary according to
the manner of their performance. Take, for example, that which we are now
doing, drinking, singing and talking—these actions are not in
themselves either good or evil, but they turn out in this or that way
according to the mode of performing them; and when well done they are
good, and when wrongly done they are evil; and in like manner not every
love, but only that which has a noble purpose, is noble and worthy of
praise. The Love who is the offspring of the common Aphrodite is
essentially common, and has no discrimination, being such as the meaner
sort of men feel, and is apt to be of women as well as of youths, and is
of the body rather than of the soul—the most foolish beings are the
objects of this love which desires only to gain an end, but never thinks
of accomplishing the end nobly, and therefore does good and evil quite
indiscriminately. The goddess who is his mother is far younger than the
other, and she was born of the union of the male and female, and partakes
of both. But the offspring of the heavenly Aphrodite is derived from a
mother in whose birth the female has no part,—she is from the male
only; this is that love which is of youths, and the goddess being older,
there is nothing of wantonness in her. Those who are inspired by this love
turn to the male, and delight in him who is the more valiant and
intelligent nature; any one may recognise the pure enthusiasts in the very
character of their attachments. For they love not boys, but intelligent
beings whose reason is beginning to be developed, much about the time at
which their beards begin to grow. And in choosing young men to be their
companions, they mean to be faithful to them, and pass their whole life in
company with them, not to take them in their inexperience, and deceive
them, and play the fool with them, or run away from one to another of
them. But the love of young boys should be forbidden by law, because their
future is uncertain; they may turn out good or bad, either in body or
soul, and much noble enthusiasm may be thrown away upon them; in this
matter the good are a law to themselves, and the coarser sort of lovers
ought to be restrained by force; as we restrain or attempt to restrain
them from fixing their affections on women of free birth. These are the
persons who bring a reproach on love; and some have been led to deny the
lawfulness of such attachments because they see the impropriety and evil
of them; for surely nothing that is decorously and lawfully done can
justly be censured. Now here and in Lacedaemon the rules about love are
perplexing, but in most cities they are simple and easily intelligible; in
Elis and Boeotia, and in countries having no gifts of eloquence, they are
very straightforward; the law is simply in favour of these connexions, and
no one, whether young or old, has anything to say to their discredit; the
reason being, as I suppose, that they are men of few words in those parts,
and therefore the lovers do not like the trouble of pleading their suit.
In Ionia and other places, and generally in countries which are subject to
the barbarians, the custom is held to be dishonourable; loves of youths
share the evil repute in which philosophy and gymnastics are held, because
they are inimical to tyranny; for the interests of rulers require that
their subjects should be poor in spirit (compare Arist. Politics), and
that there should be no strong bond of friendship or society among them,
which love, above all other motives, is likely to inspire, as our Athenian
tyrants learned by experience; for the love of Aristogeiton and the
constancy of Harmodius had a strength which undid their power. And,
therefore, the ill-repute into which these attachments have fallen is to
be ascribed to the evil condition of those who make them to be
ill-reputed; that is to say, to the self-seeking of the governors and the
cowardice of the governed; on the other hand, the indiscriminate honour
which is given to them in some countries is attributable to the laziness
of those who hold this opinion of them. In our own country a far better
principle prevails, but, as I was saying, the explanation of it is rather
perplexing. For, observe that open loves are held to be more honourable
than secret ones, and that the love of the noblest and highest, even if
their persons are less beautiful than others, is especially honourable.
Consider, too, how great is the encouragement which all the world gives to
the lover; neither is he supposed to be doing anything dishonourable; but
if he succeeds he is praised, and if he fail he is blamed. And in the
pursuit of his love the custom of mankind allows him to do many strange
things, which philosophy would bitterly censure if they were done from any
motive of interest, or wish for office or power. He may pray, and entreat,
and supplicate, and swear, and lie on a mat at the door, and endure a
slavery worse than that of any slave—in any other case friends and
enemies would be equally ready to prevent him, but now there is no friend
who will be ashamed of him and admonish him, and no enemy will charge him
with meanness or flattery; the actions of a lover have a grace which
ennobles them; and custom has decided that they are highly commendable and
that there no loss of character in them; and, what is strangest of all, he
only may swear and forswear himself (so men say), and the gods will
forgive his transgression, for there is no such thing as a lover's oath.
Such is the entire liberty which gods and men have allowed the lover,
according to the custom which prevails in our part of the world. From this
point of view a man fairly argues that in Athens to love and to be loved
is held to be a very honourable thing. But when parents forbid their sons
to talk with their lovers, and place them under a tutor's care, who is
appointed to see to these things, and their companions and equals cast in
their teeth anything of the sort which they may observe, and their elders
refuse to silence the reprovers and do not rebuke them—any one who
reflects on all this will, on the contrary, think that we hold these
practices to be most disgraceful. But, as I was saying at first, the truth
as I imagine is, that whether such practices are honourable or whether
they are dishonourable is not a simple question; they are honourable to
him who follows them honourably, dishonourable to him who follows them
dishonourably. There is dishonour in yielding to the evil, or in an evil
manner; but there is honour in yielding to the good, or in an honourable
manner. Evil is the vulgar lover who loves the body rather than the soul,
inasmuch as he is not even stable, because he loves a thing which is in
itself unstable, and therefore when the bloom of youth which he was
desiring is over, he takes wing and flies away, in spite of all his words
and promises; whereas the love of the noble disposition is life-long, for
it becomes one with the everlasting. The custom of our country would have
both of them proven well and truly, and would have us yield to the one
sort of lover and avoid the other, and therefore encourages some to
pursue, and others to fly; testing both the lover and beloved in contests
and trials, until they show to which of the two classes they respectively
belong. And this is the reason why, in the first place, a hasty attachment
is held to be dishonourable, because time is the true test of this as of
most other things; and secondly there is a dishonour in being overcome by
the love of money, or of wealth, or of political power, whether a man is
frightened into surrender by the loss of them, or, having experienced the
benefits of money and political corruption, is unable to rise above the
seductions of them. For none of these things are of a permanent or lasting
nature; not to mention that no generous friendship ever sprang from them.
There remains, then, only one way of honourable attachment which custom
allows in the beloved, and this is the way of virtue; for as we admitted
that any service which the lover does to him is not to be accounted
flattery or a dishonour to himself, so the beloved has one way only of
voluntary service which is not dishonourable, and this is virtuous
service.</p>
<p>For we have a custom, and according to our custom any one who does service
to another under the idea that he will be improved by him either in
wisdom, or in some other particular of virtue—such a voluntary
service, I say, is not to be regarded as a dishonour, and is not open to
the charge of flattery. And these two customs, one the love of youth, and
the other the practice of philosophy and virtue in general, ought to meet
in one, and then the beloved may honourably indulge the lover. For when
the lover and beloved come together, having each of them a law, and the
lover thinks that he is right in doing any service which he can to his
gracious loving one; and the other that he is right in showing any
kindness which he can to him who is making him wise and good; the one
capable of communicating wisdom and virtue, the other seeking to acquire
them with a view to education and wisdom, when the two laws of love are
fulfilled and meet in one—then, and then only, may the beloved yield
with honour to the lover. Nor when love is of this disinterested sort is
there any disgrace in being deceived, but in every other case there is
equal disgrace in being or not being deceived. For he who is gracious to
his lover under the impression that he is rich, and is disappointed of his
gains because he turns out to be poor, is disgraced all the same: for he
has done his best to show that he would give himself up to any one's 'uses
base' for the sake of money; but this is not honourable. And on the same
principle he who gives himself to a lover because he is a good man, and in
the hope that he will be improved by his company, shows himself to be
virtuous, even though the object of his affection turn out to be a
villain, and to have no virtue; and if he is deceived he has committed a
noble error. For he has proved that for his part he will do anything for
anybody with a view to virtue and improvement, than which there can be
nothing nobler. Thus noble in every case is the acceptance of another for
the sake of virtue. This is that love which is the love of the heavenly
godess, and is heavenly, and of great price to individuals and cities,
making the lover and the beloved alike eager in the work of their own
improvement. But all other loves are the offspring of the other, who is
the common goddess. To you, Phaedrus, I offer this my contribution in
praise of love, which is as good as I could make extempore.</p>
<p>Pausanias came to a pause—this is the balanced way in which I have
been taught by the wise to speak; and Aristodemus said that the turn of
Aristophanes was next, but either he had eaten too much, or from some
other cause he had the hiccough, and was obliged to change turns with
Eryximachus the physician, who was reclining on the couch below him.
Eryximachus, he said, you ought either to stop my hiccough, or to speak in
my turn until I have left off.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />