<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0015" id="link2HCH0015"></SPAN></p>
<h2> Chapter VII: Political Jurisdiction In The United States </h2>
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0016" id="link2HCH0016"></SPAN></p>
<h2> Chapter Summary </h2>
<p>Definition of political jurisdiction—What is understood by political
jurisdiction in France, in England, and in the United States—In
America the political judge can only pass sentence on public officers—He
more frequently passes a sentence of removal from office than a penalty—Political
jurisdiction as it exists in the United States is, notwithstanding its
mildness, and perhaps in consequence of that mildness, a most powerful
instrument in the hands of the majority.</p>
<p>Political Jurisdiction In The United States</p>
<p>I understand, by political jurisdiction, that temporary right of
pronouncing a legal decision with which a political body may be invested.</p>
<p>In absolute governments no utility can accrue from the introduction of
extraordinary forms of procedure; the prince in whose name an offender is
prosecuted is as much the sovereign of the courts of justice as of
everything else, and the idea which is entertained of his power is of
itself a sufficient security. The only thing he has to fear is, that the
external formalities of justice should be neglected, and that his
authority should be dishonored from a wish to render it more absolute. But
in most free countries, in which the majority can never exercise the same
influence upon the tribunals as an absolute monarch, the judicial power
has occasionally been vested for a time in the representatives of the
nation. It has been thought better to introduce a temporary confusion
between the functions of the different authorities than to violate the
necessary principle of the unity of government.</p>
<p>England, France, and the United States have established this political
jurisdiction by law; and it is curious to examine the different
adaptations which these three great nations have made of the principle. In
England and in France the House of Lords and the Chambre des Paris *a
constitute the highest criminal court of their respective nations, and
although they do not habitually try all political offences, they are
competent to try them all. Another political body enjoys the right of
impeachment before the House of Lords: the only difference which exists
between the two countries in this respect is, that in England the Commons
may impeach whomsoever they please before the Lords, whilst in France the
Deputies can only employ this mode of prosecution against the ministers of
the Crown.</p>
<p class="foot">
a <br/> [ [As it existed under the constitutional monarchy down to 1848.]]</p>
<p>In both countries the Upper House may make use of all the existing penal
laws of the nation to punish the delinquents.</p>
<p>In the United States, as well as in Europe, one branch of the legislature
is authorized to impeach and another to judge: the House of
Representatives arraigns the offender, and the Senate awards his sentence.
But the Senate can only try such persons as are brought before it by the
House of Representatives, and those persons must belong to the class of
public functionaries. Thus the jurisdiction of the Senate is less
extensive than that of the Peers of France, whilst the right of
impeachment by the Representatives is more general than that of the
Deputies. But the great difference which exists between Europe and America
is, that in Europe political tribunals are empowered to inflict all the
dispositions of the penal code, while in America, when they have deprived
the offender of his official rank, and have declared him incapable of
filling any political office for the future, their jurisdiction terminates
and that of the ordinary tribunals begins.</p>
<p>Suppose, for instance, that the President of the United States has
committed the crime of high treason; the House of Representatives
impeaches him, and the Senate degrades him; he must then be tried by a
jury, which alone can deprive him of his liberty or his life. This
accurately illustrates the subject we are treating. The political
jurisdiction which is established by the laws of Europe is intended to try
great offenders, whatever may be their birth, their rank, or their powers
in the State; and to this end all the privileges of the courts of justice
are temporarily extended to a great political assembly. The legislator is
then transformed into the magistrate; he is called upon to admit, to
distinguish, and to punish the offence; and as he exercises all the
authority of a judge, the law restricts him to the observance of all the
duties of that high office, and of all the formalities of justice. When a
public functionary is impeached before an English or a French political
tribunal, and is found guilty, the sentence deprives him ipso facto of his
functions, and it may pronounce him to be incapable of resuming them or
any others for the future. But in this case the political interdict is a
consequence of the sentence, and not the sentence itself. In Europe the
sentence of a political tribunal is to be regarded as a judicial verdict
rather than as an administrative measure. In the United States the
contrary takes place; and although the decision of the Senate is judicial
in its form, since the Senators are obliged to comply with the practices
and formalities of a court of justice; although it is judicial in respect
to the motives on which it is founded, since the Senate is in general
obliged to take an offence at common law as the basis of its sentence;
nevertheless the object of the proceeding is purely administrative. If it
had been the intention of the American legislator to invest a political
body with great judicial authority, its action would not have been limited
to the circle of public functionaries, since the most dangerous enemies of
the State may be in the possession of no functions at all; and this is
especially true in republics, where party influence is the first of
authorities, and where the strength of many a reader is increased by his
exercising no legal power.</p>
<p>If it had been the intention of the American legislator to give society
the means of repressing State offences by exemplary punishment, according
to the practice of ordinary justice, the resources of the penal code would
all have been placed at the disposal of the political tribunals. But the
weapon with which they are intrusted is an imperfect one, and it can never
reach the most dangerous offenders, since men who aim at the entire
subversion of the laws are not likely to murmur at a political interdict.</p>
<p>The main object of the political jurisdiction which obtains in the United
States is, therefore, to deprive the ill-disposed citizen of an authority
which he has used amiss, and to prevent him from ever acquiring it again.
This is evidently an administrative measure sanctioned by the formalities
of a judicial decision. In this matter the Americans have created a mixed
system; they have surrounded the act which removes a public functionary
with the securities of a political trial; and they have deprived all
political condemnations of their severest penalties. Every link of the
system may easily be traced from this point; we at once perceive why the
American constitutions subject all the civil functionaries to the
jurisdiction of the Senate, whilst the military, whose crimes are
nevertheless more formidable, are exempted from that tribunal. In the
civil service none of the American functionaries can be said to be
removable; the places which some of them occupy are inalienable, and the
others are chosen for a term which cannot be shortened. It is therefore
necessary to try them all in order to deprive them of their authority. But
military officers are dependent on the chief magistrate of the State, who
is himself a civil functionary, and the decision which condemns him is a
blow upon them all.</p>
<p>If we now compare the American and the European systems, we shall meet
with differences no less striking in the different effects which each of
them produces or may produce. In France and in England the jurisdiction of
political bodies is looked upon as an extraordinary resource, which is
only to be employed in order to rescue society from unwonted dangers. It
is not to be denied that these tribunals, as they are constituted in
Europe, are apt to violate the conservative principle of the balance of
power in the State, and to threaten incessantly the lives and liberties of
the subject. The same political jurisdiction in the United States is only
indirectly hostile to the balance of power; it cannot menace the lives of
the citizens, and it does not hover, as in Europe, over the heads of the
community, since those only who have submitted to its authority on
accepting office are exposed to the severity of its investigations. It is
at the same time less formidable and less efficacious; indeed, it has not
been considered by the legislators of the United States as a remedy for
the more violent evils of society, but as an ordinary means of conducting
the government. In this respect it probably exercises more real influence
on the social body in America than in Europe. We must not be misled by the
apparent mildness of the American legislation in all that relates to
political jurisdiction. It is to be observed, in the first place, that in
the United States the tribunal which passes sentence is composed of the
same elements, and subject to the same influences, as the body which
impeaches the offender, and that this uniformity gives an almost
irresistible impulse to the vindictive passions of parties. If political
judges in the United States cannot inflict such heavy penalties as those
of Europe, there is the less chance of their acquitting a prisoner; and
the conviction, if it is less formidable, is more certain. The principal
object of the political tribunals of Europe is to punish the offender; the
purpose of those in America is to deprive him of his authority. A
political condemnation in the United States may, therefore, be looked upon
as a preventive measure; and there is no reason for restricting the judges
to the exact definitions of criminal law. Nothing can be more alarming
than the excessive latitude with which political offences are described in
the laws of America. Article II., Section 4, of the Constitution of the
United States runs thus:—"The President, Vice-President, and all
civil officers of the United States shall be removed from office on
impeachment for, and conviction of, treason, bribery, or other high crimes
and misdemeanors." Many of the Constitutions of the States are even less
explicit. "Public officers," says the Constitution of Massachusetts, *b
"shall be impeached for misconduct or maladministration;" the Constitution
of Virginia declares that all the civil officers who shall have offended
against the State, by maladministration, corruption, or other high crimes,
may be impeached by the House of Delegates; in some constitutions no
offences are specified, in order to subject the public functionaries to an
unlimited responsibility. *c But I will venture to affirm that it is
precisely their mildness which renders the American laws most formidable
in this respect. We have shown that in Europe the removal of a functionary
and his political interdiction are the consequences of the penalty he is
to undergo, and that in America they constitute the penalty itself. The
consequence is that in Europe political tribunals are invested with rights
which they are afraid to use, and that the fear of punishing too much
hinders them from punishing at all. But in America no one hesitates to
inflict a penalty from which humanity does not recoil. To condemn a
political opponent to death, in order to deprive him of his power, is to
commit what all the world would execrate as a horrible assassination; but
to declare that opponent unworthy to exercise that authority, to deprive
him of it, and to leave him uninjured in life and limb, may be judged to
be the fair issue of the struggle. But this sentence, which it is so easy
to pronounce, is not the less fatally severe to the majority of those upon
whom it is inflicted. Great criminals may undoubtedly brave its intangible
rigor, but ordinary offenders will dread it as a condemnation which
destroys their position in the world, casts a blight upon their honor, and
condemns them to a shameful inactivity worse than death. The influence
exercised in the United States upon the progress of society by the
jurisdiction of political bodies may not appear to be formidable, but it
is only the more immense. It does not directly coerce the subject, but it
renders the majority more absolute over those in power; it does not confer
an unbounded authority on the legislator which can be exerted at some
momentous crisis, but it establishes a temperate and regular influence,
which is at all times available. If the power is decreased, it can, on the
other hand, be more conveniently employed and more easily abused. By
preventing political tribunals from inflicting judicial punishments the
Americans seem to have eluded the worst consequences of legislative
tyranny, rather than tyranny itself; and I am not sure that political
jurisdiction, as it is constituted in the United States, is not the most
formidable weapon which has ever been placed in the rude grasp of a
popular majority. When the American republics begin to degenerate it will
be easy to verify the truth of this observation, by remarking whether the
number of political impeachments augments.*d</p>
<p class="foot">
b <br/> [ Chap. I. sect. ii. Section 8.]</p>
<p class="foot">
c <br/> [ See the constitutions of Illinois, Maine, Connecticut, and
Georgia.]</p>
<p class="foot">
d <br/> [ See Appendix, N.</p>
<p>[The impeachment of President Andrew Johnson in 1868—which was
resorted to by his political opponents solely as a means of turning him
out of office, for it could not be contended that he had been guilty of
high crimes and misdemeanors, and he was in fact honorably acquitted and
reinstated in office—is a striking confirmation of the truth of this
remark.—Translator's Note, 1874.]]</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />