<p>A.C. <SPAN name="link2H_4_0003" id="link2H_4_0003"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> LORD BOLINGBROKE. </h2>
<p>Henry St. John, Lord Bolingbroke, was born in his family seat at
Battersea, on the 1st of October 1672, and died there on November 15th,
1751, in his 79th year. He was educated by a clergyman in an unnatural
manner, and speedily developed himself accordingly. When he left Oxford,
he was one of the handsomest men of the day—his majestic figure,
refined address, dazzling wit, and classic eloquence, made him
irresistibly the "first gentleman in Europe." Until his twenty-fourth
year, he was renowned more for the graces of his person, and the
fascination of his wild exploits, rather than possessing a due regard to
his rank and abilities. His conduct, however, was completely changed when
he became a Member of Parliament. The hopes of his friends were
resuscitated when they discovered the aptitude for business—the
ready eloquence, and the sound reasoning of the once wild St. John. He
soon became the hardest worker and the leader of the House of Commons. The
expectations of the nation rose high when night after night he spoke with
the vivacity of a poet, and the profundity of a veteran statesman on
public affairs. In 1704, he received the seals as Secretary-of-War, and
was mainly instrumental in gaining Marlborough's victories, by the
activity with which he supplied the English General with munitions of war.
On the ascendency of the Whigs, St. John resigned his office, and retired
into privacy for two years, when the Whig administration was destroyed,
and St. John re-appeared as Secretary for Foreign Affairs. His greatest
work now was the negotiation of the treaty of Utrecht. This treaty was
signed by St. John (then Lord Bolingbroke,) he being sent to Paris as the
British Plenipotentiary, and was hailed by the Parisians as a guardian
angel. To such an extent was this feeling manifested, that when he visited
the theatres every one <i>rose</i> to welcome him. So long as Queen Anne
lived, Bolingbroke's influence was paramount, but associated with him was
the Earl of Oxford, in opposition to the Whig party, and serious
differences had arisen between the rivals. Oxford-was dismissed four days
before the Queen's death, and Bolingbroke officiated in his place, until
Oxford's vacancy was filled, which all expected would be given to himself.
A stormy debate in the Privy Council so agitated the Queen, that it
shortened her life, and the Council recommended the Earl of Shrewsbury as
Premier, and with him the Whigs.</p>
<p>With the accession of George, came the impeachment of Bolingbroke by the
victorious Whigs. Knowing that it was their intention to sacrifice him to
party revenge, and that his accusers would likewise act as his judges, he
wisely withdrew himself to France. The Pretender held a mimic court at
Avignon, and a debating society at Lorraine, entitled a Parliament. He
offered Bolingbroke the office of Secretary of State, which was accepted
by him; and it was only at this time that the emanations of the exiled
Stuart's cabinet possessed either a solidity of aim, or a definite
purpose. If Louis XIV. had lived longer, he might have assisted the
Pretender, but with his death expired the hopes of that ill-fated dynasty.
Bolingbroke strove to husband the means which the Chevalier's friends had
collected, but the advice of the Duke of Ormond was listened to in
preference to Bolingbroke's. The results which Bolingbroke foretold—proceeding
rashly and failing ignominiously—both occurred. The insurrection
broke out, and failed—no other end could have been anticipated.
Intrigues were fast coiling themselves around the secretary; he was openly
blamed for the reverses in Scotland—but he was alike careless of
their wrath or its issue. One morning Ormond waited upon him with two
slips of paper from the Pretender, informing him that his services were no
longer required. After his dismissal he was impeached by the lackeys of
the Pretender under seven heads, which were widely distributed throughout
Europe. There is this anomaly in the life of Bolingbroke, witnessed in no
other Englishman: In one year he was the most powerful man in England—Secretary
of State—an exile—and then in the same year he occupied a
similar office to one who aimed at the English throne, and was impeached
by both parties.</p>
<p>For several years he occupied himself in France with philosophical
pursuits—until the year 1723—when he received a pardon, which
allowed him to return to England, but still his sequestered estates were
not returned, and this apology for a pardon was negotiated by a bribe of
£11,000 to the German Duchess of Kendal—one of the king's
mistresses.</p>
<p>Alexander Pope was Bolingbroke's constant correspondent. Pope had won the
applause of England by his poems, and was then considered the arbiter of
genius. Voltaire occupied a similar position in France. Since Pope first
laid the copy of his greatest epic at the feet of Bolingbroke, and begged
of him to correct its errors, he had gradually won himself that renown
which prosperity has endorsed. But what a unity in divergence did those
philosophers present! The calm moralism of Pope, his sweet and polished
rhyme, contrasted with the fiery wit and hissing sarcasm of the Frenchman,
more trenchant than Pope's, yet wanting his sparkling epigrams. The keen
discernment of both these men saw in Bolingbroke a master, and they ranked
by his side as twin apostles of a new and living faith. It was the
penetration of true greatness which discerned in the English peer that
sublimity of intellect they possessed themselves, without the egotism of
an imbecile rival. Bolingbroke had cherished the ethics of one, and
restrained the rancor of the other—and both men yielded to him whose
system they worshipped; and this trinity of Deists affords the noblest
example which can be evoked to prove the Harmony of Reason amidst the most
varied accomplishments. Although Pope's name occurs but seldom in the
history of Freethought—while that of Bolingbroke is emblazoned in
all its glory, and Voltaire is enshrined as its only Deity—yet we
must not forget that what is now known as the only collection of St.
John's works (the edition in five volumes by Mallet,) were written for the
instruction of Pope—sent to him in letters—discussed and
agreed to by him—so that the great essayist is as much implicated in
them as the author of the Dictionary. It is said, "In his society these
two illustrious men felt and acknowledged a superior genius; and if he had
no claim to excellence in poetry—the art in which they were so
pre-eminent—he surpassed them both in the philosophy they so much
admired."</p>
<p>For ten years after this period, he devoted himself to various political
writings, which were widely circulated; but we must waive the pleasure at
present of analyzing those, and confine our attention to the alliance
between Pope and Bolingbroke, in the new school of philosophy.</p>
<p>Bolingbroke's principal friends were Pope, Swift, Mallet, Wyndam, and
Atterbury. The first three were most in his confidence in regard to
religion: and although Pope was educated a Roman Catholic, and
occasionally conformed to that hierarchy (and like Voltaire, for peace,
died in it,) yet the philosophical letters which passed between Pope and
St. John, fully established him as a consistent Deist—an honor to
which Swift also attained, although being a dignitary of the Church: but
if doubts arise on the subject, they can easily be dispelled. General
Grimouard, in his "Essai sur Bolingbroke," says that "he was intimate with
the widow of Mallet, the poet, who was a lady of much talent and learning,
and had lived upon terms of friendship with Bolingbroke, Swift, Pope, and
many other distinguished characters of the day, who frequently met at her
house." The General adds, that the lady has been frequently heard to
declare, that these men were all equally deistical in their sentiments (<i>que
c'était une société de purs déistes</i>;) that Swift from his clerical
character was a little more reserved than the others, but he was evidently
of the same sentiments at bottom.</p>
<p>There is a remarkable passage in one of Pope's letters to Swift, which
seems rather corroborative of the General's. He is inviting Swift to come
and visit him. "The day is come," he says, "which I have often wished, but
never thought to see, when every mortal I esteem is of the same sentiments
in politics and religion." Dr. Warton remarks upon this paragraph "At this
time therefore (1733) he (Pope and Bolingbroke were of the same sentiment
in religion as well as politics);" * and Pope writing to Swift is proof
sufficient that Bolingbroke, Swift, and himself, were united in opinions.
Wherever Swift's name is known, it is associated with his spleen on
account of his not being elevated to the Episcopal Bench, when he was
promised a vacancy, which was reserved for him; but Queen Anne absolutely
refused to confer such a dignity upon the author of "Gulliver's Travels"—that
profound satire upon society and religion; and this occurring at a time
when his energetic services were so much needed in defence of the
government he so assisted by pamphleteering, satire, and wholesale
lampoons. Mr. Cooke says, "The Earl of Nottingham, in the debate upon the
Dissenters' Bill, chiefly founded his objection to the provision that the
Bishops should have the only power of licensing tutors, upon the
likelihood there was that a man who was in a fair way for becoming a
Bishop, was hardly suspected of being a Christian." This pointed allusion
to Swift passed without comment or reply in a public assembly, composed in
a great measure of his private friends and associates. This seems to
intimate that the opinion of his contemporaries was not very strong in
favor of Swift's religious principles. This may suffice to prove the
unanimity of sentiment existing among this brilliant coterie—one a
political Churchman—another the greatest poet of his age—the
third, the most accomplished statesman of his country. Although they were
united in religious conviction, it would have been certain ruin to any of
the confederates if the extent of their thoughts had reached the public
ear. The Dean wrote for the present—the poet for his age—and
the peer for the immediate benefit of his friends and a record for the
future. But they were all agreed that some code of ethics should be
promulgated, which should embody the positive speculations of Bolingbroke,
with the easy grace of Pope—the elaborate research of the
philosopher with the rhetoric of the poet. Swift coalesced in this idea,
but was, to a certain extent, ignorant of its subsequent history. It was
not thought prudent to trust Mallet and others with the secret. For this
purpose the "Essay of Man" was designed on the principles elaborated by
Bolingbroke in his private letters to Pope. It was Bolingbroke who drew up
the scheme, mapped out the arguments, and sketched the similes—it
was Pope who embellished its beauties, and turned it into rhyme. Doctor
Warton, the editor of Pope, also proves this:—"Lord Bathurst told
the Doctor that he had read the whole of the 'Essay on Man' in <i>the
handwriting of Bolingbroke</i>, and drawn up in a series of propositions
which Pope was to amplify, versify, and to illustrate." If further proofs
are required, that Bolingbroke was not only a co-partner but coadjutor
with Pope, it is found in the opening of the poem, where the poet uses the
plural in speaking of Bolingbroke—</p>
<p>"Awake, my St. John, leave all meaner things<br/>
To low ambition, and the pride of kings.<br/>
Laugh when we must, be candid when you can,<br/>
And vindicate the ways of God to man."<br/>
<br/>
* Cook's Life of Bolingbroke, 2nd vol., p. 97..<br/></p>
<p>This is sufficient to prove the partnership in the poem, and from the
generally acknowledged fact of his connection, we have no hesitation in
declaring that this poem is the grand epic of Deism, and is as much the
offspring of Bolingbroke, as his own ideas when enunciated by others.
There is not a single argument in the Essay but what is much more
elaborated in the works of Bolingbroke, while every positive argument is
reduced to a few poetic maxims in the Essay. We may as well look here for
Bolingbroke's creed, rather than amongst his prose works. There is,
however, this difference, that in the Essay there is laid down an ethical
scheme of positivism—<i>i.e.</i>, of everything in morals which can
be duly tested and nothing more: while in the prose writings of
Bolingbroke, the negative side of theology is discussed with an amount of
erudition which has never been surpassed by any of the great leaders of
Freethought. The first proposition of the Essay is based on a postulate,
upon which the whole reasoning is built. Overthrow this substratum, and
the philosophy of the Essay is overturned—admit it, and its truth is
evident; it is—</p>
<p>"What can we reason but from what we know?"</p>
<p>This is equivalent to saying that we can only reason concerning man as a
finite part of an infinite existence, and we can only predicate respecting
what comes under the <i>category of positive knowledge </i>; we are
therefore disabled from speculating in any theories which have for a basis
opposition to the collected experience of mankind. This was a position
laid down by Bolingbroke to escape all the historical arguments which some
men deduce from alleged miraculous agency in the past, or problematical
prophecy in the future. It <i>likewise</i> shows the untenable nature of
all analogy, which presumes to trace an hypothetical first cause or
personal intelligence, to account for a supposed origin of primeval
existence, by which nature was caused, or forms of being first evolved.
Although it may be deemed inconsistent with the philosophy of Bolingbroke
to admit a God in the same argument as the above, we must not forget that
in all speculative reasoning there must be an assumption of some kind,
which ought to be demonstrated by proof, or a suitable equivalent in the
form of universal consent. Yet in the case of the God of the Essay, we
look in vain for the attributes with which Theists love to clothe their
God, and we can but perceive inexorable necessity in the shape of rigid
and unswerving laws, collected in one focus by Pope, and dignified with
the name of God; so that the difference betwixt a Deist of the old, and an
Atheist of the modern school, is one of mere words—they both
commence with an assumption, the Atheist only defining his terms more
strictly, the subject-matter in both instances being the same. The only
difference being, the one deceives himself with a meaningless word, the
other is speechless on what he cannot comprehend. The Essay shows a scheme
of universal gradation, composed of a series of links, which are one
entwined within the other—every rock being placed in its
necessitated position—every plant amidst its growth bearing an
exoteric similitude to itself—every animal, from the lowest
quadruped to the highest race of man, occupying a range of climate adapted
to its requirements. The Essay here is scientifically correct, and agrees
with the ablest writers on necessity. A German philosopher renowned alike
for rigid analysis and transcendent abilities as a successful theorist,
observes, "When I contemplate all things as a whole, I perceive one <i>nature</i>
one <i>force </i>: when I regard them as individuals, many forces which
develop themselves according to their inward laws, and pass through all
the forms of which they are capable, and all the objects in nature are but
those forces under certain limitations. Every manifestation of every
individual power of nature is determined partly by itself, partly by its
own preceding manifestations, and partly by the manifestations of all
other powers of nature with which it is connected; but it is connected
with all, for nature is one connected whole. Its manifestations are,
therefore, strictly necessary, and it is absolutely impossible to be other
than as it is. In every moment of her duration nature is one connected
whole, in every moment must every individual be what it is because all
others are what they are, and a single grain of sand could not be moved
from its place, without, however imperceptibly to us, changing something
throughout all parts of the immeasurable whole. Every moment of duration
is determined by all past moments, and will determine all future
movements, and even the position of a grain of sand cannot be conceived
other than it is, without supposing other changes to an indefinite extent.
Let us imagine that grain of sand to be lying some few feet further inland
than it actually does; then must the storm-wind that drove it in from the
sea-shore have been stronger than it actually was; then must the preceding
state of the atmosphere, by which this wind was occasioned, and its degree
of strength being determined, have been different from what it actually
was, and the preceding changes which gave rise to this particular weather,
and so on. We must suppose a different temperature from that which really
existed—a different constitution of bodies which influenced that
temperature. How can we know that in such a state of weather we have been
supposing, in order to carry this grain of sand a few yards further, some
ancestors of yours might not have perished from hunger, cold, or heat,
long before the birth of that son from whom you are descended, and thus
you might never have been at all, and all that you have done, and all that
you ever hope to do, must have been hindered, in order that a grain of
sand might lie in a different place." * The whole of the first book is
devoted to the necessitated condition of man in relation to the universe.
In one portion there is a succession of beautiful similes, portraying the
blissful state we are in, instead of being gifted with finer
sensibilities, or a prescience, which would be a curse.</p>
<p>* Fichte's "Destination of Man," pp. 8, 9<br/></p>
<p>Pope, although an ardent disciple of Bolingbroke, did not entirely forsake
the prejudices of childhood; he still indulged in a bare hope of a future
life, which his master, with more consistency, suppressed. So that when
the poet rhymed the propositions of St. John, he pointed them with "hope"
in an eternal future; for that speculation which was still <i>probability</i>
in his day, is now nearly silenced by modern science. But we must not
confound the ideas of futurity, which some of the Deists expressed, with
those of Christianity. They were as different as the dreams of Christ and
Plato were dissimilar. Pope "hoped" for a future life of intellectual
enjoyment devoid of evil, but the heaven of the gospel is equally as
necessary to be counterbalanced by a hell, as the existence of a God
requires the balancing support of a devil. We therefore can sympathise
with the description of a heaven, the poor Indian looked for:—</p>
<p>"Some safer world in depths of woods embraced,<br/>
Some happier island in the watery waste;<br/>
Where slaves once more their native land behold,<br/>
Nor fiends torment, nor <i>Christians thirst for gold.<br/>
To be</i>—contents his natural desires,<br/>
He asks no angels' wings, no seraphs' fires,<br/>
But thinks, admitted to that equal sky,<br/>
His faithful dog should bear him company."<br/></p>
<p>Pope durst not emphatically deny the future-life theory, so he attacked it
by elaborating a physical instead of a spiritual heaven. So heterodox a
notion of the Indian's future sports, is not to be found in theology,
especially as he pictures the Indian's sports with his dog. Here was a
double blow aimed at Christianity by evolving a "positive" idea of future
pleasures, and the promulgation of sentiments anti-Christian.—Again
he attacks them for unwarrantable speculation in theology, when he says—</p>
<p>"In pride, in reasoning pride our error lies."<br/></p>
<p>This is a corollary to the first proposition, "What can we reason but from
what we know?" The only predicate we can draw from this is, the undoubted
fact we have no right to profess to hold opinions of that, upon which we
cannot have any positive proof. The last line of the first book has been
generally thought open to attack. It relates to necessity—"Whatever
is, is right"—and is not to be viewed in relation to society as at
present constituted, but to the physical universe.</p>
<p>The second book deals with man in relation to himself as an individual;
the third as a member of society, and the last in respect to happiness.
Throughout the whole Essay the distinctions arising from nature and
instinct are defined and defended with vigor and acuteness. Both are
proved to be equally great in degree, in spite of the hints constantly
thrown out in reference to "God-like Reason <i>versus</i> Blind Instinct."
We confess our inability to discern the vaunted superiority of the powers
of reason over those of its blinder sister. We see in the one matchless
wisdom—profound decision—unfailing resource—a happy
contentment as unfeigned as it is natural. On the other hand, we see
temerity allied with cowardice—a man seeking wisdom on a watery
plank, when every footmark may serve him for a funeral effigy; political
duplicity arising from his confined generalization of facts; a desire to
do right, but checked by accident and cunning—everywhere uneasy—always
fatal. If the Christians' fables were true, we might say that Adam and Eve
were originally in possession of Instinct and Reason, and fell by
listening to the promptings of volition, instead of the unswerving powers
of the brutes, and for a hereditary punishment was cursed with a
superabundance of reason. For with all our intellectual prerogatives, we
have yet failed to arrive at a definite course of action which should
influence our conduct. The Essay, speaking of Government by Christianity,
says:—</p>
<p>"Force first made conquest, and that conquest law,<br/>
Till superstition taught the tyrant awe.<br/>
<br/>
.....<br/>
<br/>
She taught the weak to bend, the proud to pray,<br/>
To power unseen, and mightier far than they:<br/>
She, from the rending earth and bursting skies,<br/>
Saw Gods descend and fiends infernal rise.<br/>
Here <i>fixed</i> the dreadful, there the blessed abodes,<br/>
Here <i>made her</i> devils, and weak hope her Gods.<br/>
Gods partial, changeful, passionate, <i>unjust</i>,<br/>
Whose <i>attributes were rage, revenge, or lust</i>.<br/>
Such as the souls of cowards might conceive,<br/>
And formed like tyrants; tyrants would believe.<br/>
Zeal then, not charity, became the guide,<br/>
And Hell was <i>built in spite</i>, and Heaven in pride."<br/></p>
<p>And again—</p>
<p>"For modes of faith let graceless zealots fight,<br/>
His can't be wrong whose life is in the right."<br/></p>
<p>The Essay concludes with an invocation to Bolingbroke—whom Pope
styles, "my guide, philosopher, and friend." Such is the conclusion of the
most remarkable ethical poem in any language. It is the Iliad of English
Deism. Not a single allusion to Christ—a future state of existence
given only as a faint probability—the whole artificial state of
society satirized—prayer ridiculed, and government of every kind
denounced which does not bring happiness to the people. The first
principle laid down is the corner-stone of materialism—"What can we
reason but from what we know?"—which is stated, explained, and
defended with an axiomatic brevity rarely equalled, never surpassed—with
a number of illustrations comprising the <i>chef d'oeuvre</i> of poetic
grace, and synthical melody combined with arguments as cogent as the
examples are perfect.</p>
<p>It stands alone in its impregnability—a pile of literary
architecture like the "Novum Organan" of Bacon, the "Principia" of Newton,
or the Essay of Locke. The facades of its noble colonnades are seen
extending their wings through the whole sweep of history, constituting a
pantheon of morals, where every nation sends its devotees to admire and
worship.</p>
<p>Let us now turn to the philosophical works of Bolingbroke. By the will of
Bolingbroke he devised this portion of his manuscripts to David Mallet,
the poet, for publication. The noble Lord's choice is open to censure
here. He knew the character of Mallet, and could expect little justice
from him who should have been his biographer. The MSS. were all prepared
for the press long before Bolingbroke died. In this original state, they
were addressed to Pope. When published they appeared as "Letters or Essays
addressed to Alexander Pope, Esq." The political friends of St. John
wished their suppression, fearing that they would injure his reputation by
being anti-Christian. A large bribe was offered by Lord Cornbur if Mallet
would destroy the works. He, no doubt, thinking more money could be made
by their publication, issued them to the world in 1754, but without giving
a biography or notes to the books, his work being simply correcting the
errors of the press. True, there existed no stipulation that he should
write the Life of Bolingbroke, but no one can doubt that such was the
intention of the statesman, when he bequeathed to him property which
realized £10,000 in value. Every one knows the huge witticism of Dr.
Johnson, who accused Bolingbroke of cowardice, under the simile of loading
a blunderbuss, and then leaving a Scotchman half-a-crown to fire it when
he was out of the way. When those posthumous works appeared, the grand
jury of Westminster presented them to the judicial authorities as
subversive of religion, morality, and government. They were burnt by the
common hangman.</p>
<p>With difficulty we give a quotation from Boling-broke's ideas of a Future
Life. In vol. IV., p. 348, he says, "I do not say, that to believe in a
future state is to believe in a vulgar error; but this I say, it cannot be
demonstrated by reason: it is not in the nature of it capable of
demonstration, and no one ever returned that irremediable way to give us
an assurance of the fact."</p>
<p>Again, he speaks personally in reference to himself, Pope, and Wollaston,
whom he had been opposing:—</p>
<p>"He alone is happy, and he 'is truly so, who can say,<br/>
Welcome life whatever it brings!<br/>
Welcome death whatever it is!<br/>
If the former,—we change our state.<br/>
<br/>
.....<br/></p>
<p>That you, or I, or even Wollaston himself, should return to the earth from
whence we came, to the dirt under our feet, or be mingled with the ashes
of those herbs and plants from which we drew nutrition whilst we lived,
does not seem any indignity offered to our nature, since it is common to
all the animal kind: and he who complains of it as such, does not seem to
have been set, by his reasoning faculties, so far above them in life; as
to deserve not to be levelled with them at death. We were like them before
our birth, that is nothing. So we shall be on this hypothesis, like them
too after our death, that is nothing. What hardship is done us? Unless it
be a hardship, that we are not immortal because we wish to be so, and
flatter ourselves with that expectation.</p>
<p>"If this hypothesis were true, which I am far from assuming, I should have
no reason to complain, though having tasted existence, I might abhor
non-entity. Since, then, the first cannot be demonstrated by reason, nor
the second be reconciled to my inward sentiment, let me take refuge in
resignation at the last, as in every other act of my life: let others be
solicitous about their future state, and frighten or flatter themselves as
prejudice, imaginative bad health—nay, a lowering day, or a clear
sunshine shall inspire them to do: let the tranquillity of my mind rest on
this immovable rock, that my future, as well as my present state, are
ordered by an Almighty Creator, and that they are equally foolish, and
presumptuous, who make imaginary excursions into futurity, and who
complain of the present."</p>
<p>Lord Bolingbroke died in the year 1751, after a long and painful illness,
occasioned by the ignorance of a quack. While lying on his death-bed he
composed a discourse, entitled "Considerations on the State of the
Nation." He died in peace—in the knowledge of the truth of the
principles he had advocated, and with that calm serenity of mind, which no
one can more fully experience than the honest Freethinker. He was buried
in the church at Battersea. He was a man of the highest rank of genius,
far from being immaculate in his youth, brave, sincere, a true friend,
possessed of rich learning, a clear and sparkling style, a great wit, and
the most powerful Freethinker of his age.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />