<p>Now, I have said that the community by means of organisation of machinery
will supply the useful things, and that the beautiful things will be
made by the individual. This is not merely necessary, but it is
the only possible way by which we can get either the one or the other.
An individual who has to make things for the use of others, and with
reference to their wants and their wishes, does not work with interest,
and consequently cannot put into his work what is best in him.
Upon the other hand, whenever a community or a powerful section of a
community, or a government of any kind, attempts to dictate to the artist
what he is to do, Art either entirely vanishes, or becomes stereotyped,
or degenerates into a low and ignoble form of craft. A work of
art is the unique result of a unique temperament. Its beauty comes
from the fact that the author is what he is. It has nothing to
do with the fact that other people want what they want. Indeed,
the moment that an artist takes notice of what other people want, and
tries to supply the demand, he ceases to be an artist, and becomes a
dull or an amusing craftsman, an honest or a dishonest tradesman.
He has no further claim to be considered as an artist. Art is
the most intense mode of Individualism that the world has known.
I am inclined to say that it is the only real mode of Individualism
that the world has known. Crime, which, under certain conditions,
may seem to have created Individualism, must take cognisance of other
people and interfere with them. It belongs to the sphere of action.
But alone, without any reference to his neighbours, without any interference,
the artist can fashion a beautiful thing; and if he does not do it solely
for his own pleasure, he is not an artist at all.</p>
<p>And it is to be noted that it is the fact that Art is this intense
form of Individualism that makes the public try to exercise over it
in an authority that is as immoral as it is ridiculous, and as corrupting
as it is contemptible. It is not quite their fault. The
public has always, and in every age, been badly brought up. They
are continually asking Art to be popular, to please their want of taste,
to flatter their absurd vanity, to tell them what they have been told
before, to show them what they ought to be tired of seeing, to amuse
them when they feel heavy after eating too much, and to distract their
thoughts when they are wearied of their own stupidity. Now Art
should never try to be popular. The public should try to make
itself artistic. There is a very wide difference. If a man
of science were told that the results of his experiments, and the conclusions
that he arrived at, should be of such a character that they would not
upset the received popular notions on the subject, or disturb popular
prejudice, or hurt the sensibilities of people who knew nothing about
science; if a philosopher were told that he had a perfect right to speculate
in the highest spheres of thought, provided that he arrived at the same
conclusions as were held by those who had never thought in any sphere
at all—well, nowadays the man of science and the philosopher would
be considerably amused. Yet it is really a very few years since
both philosophy and science were subjected to brutal popular control,
to authority—in fact the authority of either the general ignorance
of the community, or the terror and greed for power of an ecclesiastical
or governmental class. Of course, we have to a very great extent
got rid of any attempt on the part of the community, or the Church,
or the Government, to interfere with the individualism of speculative
thought, but the attempt to interfere with the individualism of imaginative
art still lingers. In fact, it does more than linger; it is aggressive,
offensive, and brutalising.</p>
<p>In England, the arts that have escaped best are the arts in which
the public take no interest. Poetry is an instance of what I mean.
We have been able to have fine poetry in England because the public
do not read it, and consequently do not influence it. The public
like to insult poets because they are individual, but once they have
insulted them, they leave them alone. In the case of the novel
and the drama, arts in which the public do take an interest, the result
of the exercise of popular authority has been absolutely ridiculous.
No country produces such badly-written fiction, such tedious, common
work in the novel form, such silly, vulgar plays as England. It
must necessarily be so. The popular standard is of such a character
that no artist can get to it. It is at once too easy and too difficult
to be a popular novelist. It is too easy, because the requirements
of the public as far as plot, style, psychology, treatment of life,
and treatment of literature are concerned are within the reach of the
very meanest capacity and the most uncultivated mind. It is too
difficult, because to meet such requirements the artist would have to
do violence to his temperament, would have to write not for the artistic
joy of writing, but for the amusement of half-educated people, and so
would have to suppress his individualism, forget his culture, annihilate
his style, and surrender everything that is valuable in him. In
the case of the drama, things are a little better: the theatre-going
public like the obvious, it is true, but they do not like the tedious;
and burlesque and farcical comedy, the two most popular forms, are distinct
forms of art. Delightful work may be produced under burlesque
and farcical conditions, and in work of this kind the artist in England
is allowed very great freedom. It is when one comes to the higher
forms of the drama that the result of popular control is seen.
The one thing that the public dislike is novelty. Any attempt
to extend the subject-matter of art is extremely distasteful to the
public; and yet the vitality and progress of art depend in a large measure
on the continual extension of subject-matter. The public dislike
novelty because they are afraid of it. It represents to them a
mode of Individualism, an assertion on the part of the artist that he
selects his own subject, and treats it as he chooses. The public
are quite right in their attitude. Art is Individualism, and Individualism
is a disturbing and disintegrating force. Therein lies its immense
value. For what it seeks to disturb is monotony of type, slavery
of custom, tyranny of habit, and the reduction of man to the level of
a machine. In Art, the public accept what has been, because they
cannot alter it, not because they appreciate it. They swallow
their classics whole, and never taste them. They endure them as
the inevitable, and as they cannot mar them, they mouth about them.
Strangely enough, or not strangely, according to one’s own views,
this acceptance of the classics does a great deal of harm. The
uncritical admiration of the Bible and Shakespeare in England is an
instance of what I mean. With regard to the Bible, considerations
of ecclesiastical authority enter into the matter, so that I need not
dwell upon the point. But in the case of Shakespeare it is quite
obvious that the public really see neither the beauties nor the defects
of his plays. If they saw the beauties, they would not object
to the development of the drama; and if they saw the defects, they would
not object to the development of the drama either. The fact is,
the public make use of the classics of a country as a means of checking
the progress of Art. They degrade the classics into authorities.
They use them as bludgeons for preventing the free expression of Beauty
in new forms. They are always asking a writer why he does not
write like somebody else, or a painter why he does not paint like somebody
else, quite oblivious of the fact that if either of them did anything
of the kind he would cease to be an artist. A fresh mode of Beauty
is absolutely distasteful to them, and whenever it appears they get
so angry, and bewildered that they always use two stupid expressions—one
is that the work of art is grossly unintelligible; the other, that the
work of art is grossly immoral. What they mean by these words
seems to me to be this. When they say a work is grossly unintelligible,
they mean that the artist has said or made a beautiful thing that is
new; when they describe a work as grossly immoral, they mean that the
artist has said or made a beautiful thing that is true. The former
expression has reference to style; the latter to subject-matter.
But they probably use the words very vaguely, as an ordinary mob will
use ready-made paving-stones. There is not a single real poet
or prose-writer of this century, for instance, on whom the British public
have not solemnly conferred diplomas of immorality, and these diplomas
practically take the place, with us, of what in France, is the formal
recognition of an Academy of Letters, and fortunately make the establishment
of such an institution quite unnecessary in England. Of course,
the public are very reckless in their use of the word. That they
should have called Wordsworth an immoral poet, was only to be expected.
Wordsworth was a poet. But that they should have called Charles
Kingsley an immoral novelist is extraordinary. Kingsley’s
prose was not of a very fine quality. Still, there is the word,
and they use it as best they can. An artist is, of course, not
disturbed by it. The true artist is a man who believes absolutely
in himself, because he is absolutely himself. But I can fancy
that if an artist produced a work of art in England that immediately
on its appearance was recognised by the public, through their medium,
which is the public press, as a work that was quite intelligible and
highly moral, he would begin to seriously question whether in its creation
he had really been himself at all, and consequently whether the work
was not quite unworthy of him, and either of a thoroughly second-rate
order, or of no artistic value whatsoever.</p>
<p>Perhaps, however, I have wronged the public in limiting them to such
words as ‘immoral,’ ‘unintelligible,’ ‘exotic,’
and ‘unhealthy.’ There is one other word that they
use. That word is ‘morbid.’ They do not use
it often. The meaning of the word is so simple that they are afraid
of using it. Still, they use it sometimes, and, now and then,
one comes across it in popular newspapers. It is, of course, a
ridiculous word to apply to a work of art. For what is morbidity
but a mood of emotion or a mode of thought that one cannot express?
The public are all morbid, because the public can never find expression
for anything. The artist is never morbid. He expresses everything.
He stands outside his subject, and through its medium produces incomparable
and artistic effects. To call an artist morbid because he deals
with morbidity as his subject-matter is as silly as if one called Shakespeare
mad because he wrote ‘King Lear.’</p>
<p>On the whole, an artist in England gains something by being attacked.
His individuality is intensified. He becomes more completely himself.
Of course, the attacks are very gross, very impertinent, and very contemptible.
But then no artist expects grace from the vulgar mind, or style from
the suburban intellect. Vulgarity and stupidity are two very vivid
facts in modern life. One regrets them, naturally. But there
they are. They are subjects for study, like everything else.
And it is only fair to state, with regard to modern journalists, that
they always apologise to one in private for what they have written against
one in public.</p>
<p>Within the last few years two other adjectives, it may be mentioned,
have been added to the very limited vocabulary of art-abuse that is
at the disposal of the public. One is the word ‘unhealthy,’
the other is the word ‘exotic.’ The latter merely
expresses the rage of the momentary mushroom against the immortal, entrancing,
and exquisitely lovely orchid. It is a tribute, but a tribute
of no importance. The word ‘unhealthy,’ however, admits
of analysis. It is a rather interesting word. In fact, it
is so interesting that the people who use it do not know what it means.</p>
<p>What does it mean? What is a healthy, or an unhealthy work
of art? All terms that one applies to a work of art, provided
that one applies them rationally, have reference to either its style
or its subject, or to both together. From the point of view of
style, a healthy work of art is one whose style recognises the beauty
of the material it employs, be that material one of words or of bronze,
of colour or of ivory, and uses that beauty as a factor in producing
the aesthetic effect. From the point of view of subject, a healthy
work of art is one the choice of whose subject is conditioned by the
temperament of the artist, and comes directly out of it. In fine,
a healthy work of art is one that has both perfection and personality.
Of course, form and substance cannot be separated in a work of art;
they are always one. But for purposes of analysis, and setting
the wholeness of aesthetic impression aside for a moment, we can intellectually
so separate them. An unhealthy work of art, on the other hand,
is a work whose style is obvious, old-fashioned, and common, and whose
subject is deliberately chosen, not because the artist has any pleasure
in it, but because he thinks that the public will pay him for it.
In fact, the popular novel that the public calls healthy is always a
thoroughly unhealthy production; and what the public call an unhealthy
novel is always a beautiful and healthy work of art.</p>
<p>I need hardly say that I am not, for a single moment, complaining
that the public and the public press misuse these words. I do
not see how, with their lack of comprehension of what Art is, they could
possibly use them in the proper sense. I am merely pointing out
the misuse; and as for the origin of the misuse and the meaning that
lies behind it all, the explanation is very simple. It comes from
the barbarous conception of authority. It comes from the natural
inability of a community corrupted by authority to understand or appreciate
Individualism. In a word, it comes from that monstrous and ignorant
thing that is called Public Opinion, which, bad and well-meaning as
it is when it tries to control action, is infamous and of evil meaning
when it tries to control Thought or Art.</p>
<p>Indeed, there is much more to be said in favour of the physical force
of the public than there is in favour of the public’s opinion.
The former may be fine. The latter must be foolish. It is
often said that force is no argument. That, however, entirely
depends on what one wants to prove. Many of the most important
problems of the last few centuries, such as the continuance of personal
government in England, or of feudalism in France, have been solved entirely
by means of physical force. The very violence of a revolution
may make the public grand and splendid for a moment. It was a
fatal day when the public discovered that the pen is mightier than the
paving-stone, and can be made as offensive as the brickbat. They
at once sought for the journalist, found him, developed him, and made
him their industrious and well-paid servant. It is greatly to
be regretted, for both their sakes. Behind the barricade there
may be much that is noble and heroic. But what is there behind
the leading-article but prejudice, stupidity, cant, and twaddle?
And when these four are joined together they make a terrible force,
and constitute the new authority.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />