<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0012" id="link2HCH0012"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Chapter Twelve: Thinking in Education </h2>
<p>1. The Essentials of Method. No one doubts, theoretically, the importance
of fostering in school good habits of thinking. But apart from the fact
that the acknowledgment is not so great in practice as in theory, there is
not adequate theoretical recognition that all which the school can or need
do for pupils, so far as their minds are concerned (that is, leaving out
certain specialized muscular abilities), is to develop their ability to
think. The parceling out of instruction among various ends such as
acquisition of skill (in reading, spelling, writing, drawing, reciting);
acquiring information (in history and geography), and training of thinking
is a measure of the ineffective way in which we accomplish all three.
Thinking which is not connected with increase of efficiency in action, and
with learning more about ourselves and the world in which we live, has
something the matter with it just as thought (See ante, p. 147). And skill
obtained apart from thinking is not connected with any sense of the
purposes for which it is to be used. It consequently leaves a man at the
mercy of his routine habits and of the authoritative control of others,
who know what they are about and who are not especially scrupulous as to
their means of achievement. And information severed from thoughtful action
is dead, a mind-crushing load. Since it simulates knowledge and thereby
develops the poison of conceit, it is a most powerful obstacle to further
growth in the grace of intelligence. The sole direct path to enduring
improvement in the methods of instruction and learning consists in
centering upon the conditions which exact, promote, and test thinking.
Thinking is the method of intelligent learning, of learning that employs
and rewards mind. We speak, legitimately enough, about the method of
thinking, but the important thing to bear in mind about method is that
thinking is method, the method of intelligent experience in the course
which it takes.</p>
<p>I. The initial stage of that developing experience which is called
thinking is experience. This remark may sound like a silly truism. It
ought to be one; but unfortunately it is not. On the contrary, thinking is
often regarded both in philosophic theory and in educational practice as
something cut off from experience, and capable of being cultivated in
isolation. In fact, the inherent limitations of experience are often urged
as the sufficient ground for attention to thinking. Experience is then
thought to be confined to the senses and appetites; to a mere material
world, while thinking proceeds from a higher faculty (of reason), and is
occupied with spiritual or at least literary things. So, oftentimes, a
sharp distinction is made between pure mathematics as a peculiarly fit
subject matter of thought (since it has nothing to do with physical
existences) and applied mathematics, which has utilitarian but not mental
value.</p>
<p>Speaking generally, the fundamental fallacy in methods of instruction lies
in supposing that experience on the part of pupils may be assumed. What is
here insisted upon is the necessity of an actual empirical situation as
the initiating phase of thought. Experience is here taken as previously
defined: trying to do something and having the thing perceptibly do
something to one in return. The fallacy consists in supposing that we can
begin with ready-made subject matter of arithmetic, or geography, or
whatever, irrespective of some direct personal experience of a situation.
Even the kindergarten and Montessori techniques are so anxious to get at
intellectual distinctions, without "waste of time," that they tend to
ignore—or reduce—the immediate crude handling of the familiar
material of experience, and to introduce pupils at once to material which
expresses the intellectual distinctions which adults have made. But the
first stage of contact with any new material, at whatever age of maturity,
must inevitably be of the trial and error sort. An individual must
actually try, in play or work, to do something with material in carrying
out his own impulsive activity, and then note the interaction of his
energy and that of the material employed. This is what happens when a
child at first begins to build with blocks, and it is equally what happens
when a scientific man in his laboratory begins to experiment with
unfamiliar objects.</p>
<p>Hence the first approach to any subject in school, if thought is to be
aroused and not words acquired, should be as unscholastic as possible. To
realize what an experience, or empirical situation, means, we have to call
to mind the sort of situation that presents itself outside of school; the
sort of occupations that interest and engage activity in ordinary life.
And careful inspection of methods which are permanently successful in
formal education, whether in arithmetic or learning to read, or studying
geography, or learning physics or a foreign language, will reveal that
they depend for their efficiency upon the fact that they go back to the
type of the situation which causes reflection out of school in ordinary
life. They give the pupils something to do, not something to learn; and
the doing is of such a nature as to demand thinking, or the intentional
noting of connections; learning naturally results.</p>
<p>That the situation should be of such a nature as to arouse thinking means
of course that it should suggest something to do which is not either
routine or capricious—something, in other words, presenting what is
new (and hence uncertain or problematic) and yet sufficiently connected
with existing habits to call out an effective response. An effective
response means one which accomplishes a perceptible result, in distinction
from a purely haphazard activity, where the consequences cannot be
mentally connected with what is done. The most significant question which
can be asked, accordingly, about any situation or experience proposed to
induce learning is what quality of problem it involves.</p>
<p>At first thought, it might seem as if usual school methods measured well
up to the standard here set. The giving of problems, the putting of
questions, the assigning of tasks, the magnifying of difficulties, is a
large part of school work. But it is indispensable to discriminate between
genuine and simulated or mock problems. The following questions may aid in
making such discrimination. (a) Is there anything but a problem? Does the
question naturally suggest itself within some situation or personal
experience? Or is it an aloof thing, a problem only for the purposes of
conveying instruction in some school topic? Is it the sort of trying that
would arouse observation and engage experimentation outside of school? (b)
Is it the pupil's own problem, or is it the teacher's or textbook's
problem, made a problem for the pupil only because he cannot get the
required mark or be promoted or win the teacher's approval, unless he
deals with it? Obviously, these two questions overlap. They are two ways
of getting at the same point: Is the experience a personal thing of such a
nature as inherently to stimulate and direct observation of the
connections involved, and to lead to inference and its testing? Or is it
imposed from without, and is the pupil's problem simply to meet the
external requirement? Such questions may give us pause in deciding upon
the extent to which current practices are adapted to develop reflective
habits. The physical equipment and arrangements of the average schoolroom
are hostile to the existence of real situations of experience. What is
there similar to the conditions of everyday life which will generate
difficulties? Almost everything testifies to the great premium put upon
listening, reading, and the reproduction of what is told and read. It is
hardly possible to overstate the contrast between such conditions and the
situations of active contact with things and persons in the home, on the
playground, in fulfilling of ordinary responsibilities of life. Much of it
is not even comparable with the questions which may arise in the mind of a
boy or girl in conversing with others or in reading books outside of the
school. No one has ever explained why children are so full of questions
outside of the school (so that they pester grown-up persons if they get
any encouragement), and the conspicuous absence of display of curiosity
about the subject matter of school lessons. Reflection on this striking
contrast will throw light upon the question of how far customary school
conditions supply a context of experience in which problems naturally
suggest themselves. No amount of improvement in the personal technique of
the instructor will wholly remedy this state of things. There must be more
actual material, more stuff, more appliances, and more opportunities for
doing things, before the gap can be overcome. And where children are
engaged in doing things and in discussing what arises in the course of
their doing, it is found, even with comparatively indifferent modes of
instruction, that children's inquiries are spontaneous and numerous, and
the proposals of solution advanced, varied, and ingenious.</p>
<p>As a consequence of the absence of the materials and occupations which
generate real problems, the pupil's problems are not his; or, rather, they
are his only as a pupil, not as a human being. Hence the lamentable waste
in carrying over such expertness as is achieved in dealing with them to
the affairs of life beyond the schoolroom. A pupil has a problem, but it
is the problem of meeting the peculiar requirements set by the teacher.
His problem becomes that of finding out what the teacher wants, what will
satisfy the teacher in recitation and examination and outward deportment.
Relationship to subject matter is no longer direct. The occasions and
material of thought are not found in the arithmetic or the history or
geography itself, but in skillfully adapting that material to the
teacher's requirements. The pupil studies, but unconsciously to himself
the objects of his study are the conventions and standards of the school
system and school authority, not the nominal "studies." The thinking thus
evoked is artificially one-sided at the best. At its worst, the problem of
the pupil is not how to meet the requirements of school life, but how to
seem to meet them—or, how to come near enough to meeting them to
slide along without an undue amount of friction. The type of judgment
formed by these devices is not a desirable addition to character. If these
statements give too highly colored a picture of usual school methods, the
exaggeration may at least serve to illustrate the point: the need of
active pursuits, involving the use of material to accomplish purposes, if
there are to be situations which normally generate problems occasioning
thoughtful inquiry.</p>
<p>II. There must be data at command to supply the considerations required in
dealing with the specific difficulty which has presented itself. Teachers
following a "developing" method sometimes tell children to think things
out for themselves as if they could spin them out of their own heads. The
material of thinking is not thoughts, but actions, facts, events, and the
relations of things. In other words, to think effectively one must have
had, or now have, experiences which will furnish him resources for coping
with the difficulty at hand. A difficulty is an indispensable stimulus to
thinking, but not all difficulties call out thinking. Sometimes they
overwhelm and submerge and discourage. The perplexing situation must be
sufficiently like situations which have already been dealt with so that
pupils will have some control of the meanings of handling it. A large part
of the art of instruction lies in making the difficulty of new problems
large enough to challenge thought, and small enough so that, in addition
to the confusion naturally attending the novel elements, there shall be
luminous familiar spots from which helpful suggestions may spring.</p>
<p>In one sense, it is a matter of indifference by what psychological means
the subject matter for reflection is provided. Memory, observation,
reading, communication, are all avenues for supplying data. The relative
proportion to be obtained from each is a matter of the specific features
of the particular problem in hand. It is foolish to insist upon
observation of objects presented to the senses if the student is so
familiar with the objects that he could just as well recall the facts
independently. It is possible to induce undue and crippling dependence
upon sense-presentations. No one can carry around with him a museum of all
the things whose properties will assist the conduct of thought. A
well-trained mind is one that has a maximum of resources behind it, so to
speak, and that is accustomed to go over its past experiences to see what
they yield. On the other hand, a quality or relation of even a familiar
object may previously have been passed over, and be just the fact that is
helpful in dealing with the question. In this case direct observation is
called for. The same principle applies to the use to be made of
observation on one hand and of reading and "telling" on the other. Direct
observation is naturally more vivid and vital. But it has its limitations;
and in any case it is a necessary part of education that one should
acquire the ability to supplement the narrowness of his immediately
personal experiences by utilizing the experiences of others. Excessive
reliance upon others for data (whether got from reading or listening) is
to be depreciated. Most objectionable of all is the probability that
others, the book or the teacher, will supply solutions ready-made, instead
of giving material that the student has to adapt and apply to the question
in hand for himself.</p>
<p>There is no inconsistency in saying that in schools there is usually both
too much and too little information supplied by others. The accumulation
and acquisition of information for purposes of reproduction in recitation
and examination is made too much of. "Knowledge," in the sense of
information, means the working capital, the indispensable resources, of
further inquiry; of finding out, or learning, more things. Frequently it
is treated as an end itself, and then the goal becomes to heap it up and
display it when called for. This static, cold-storage ideal of knowledge
is inimical to educative development. It not only lets occasions for
thinking go unused, but it swamps thinking. No one could construct a house
on ground cluttered with miscellaneous junk. Pupils who have stored their
"minds" with all kinds of material which they have never put to
intellectual uses are sure to be hampered when they try to think. They
have no practice in selecting what is appropriate, and no criterion to go
by; everything is on the same dead static level. On the other hand, it is
quite open to question whether, if information actually functioned in
experience through use in application to the student's own purposes, there
would not be need of more varied resources in books, pictures, and talks
than are usually at command.</p>
<p>III. The correlate in thinking of facts, data, knowledge already acquired,
is suggestions, inferences, conjectured meanings, suppositions, tentative
explanations:—ideas, in short. Careful observation and recollection
determine what is given, what is already there, and hence assured. They
cannot furnish what is lacking. They define, clarify, and locate the
question; they cannot supply its answer. Projection, invention, ingenuity,
devising come in for that purpose. The data arouse suggestions, and only
by reference to the specific data can we pass upon the appropriateness of
the suggestions. But the suggestions run beyond what is, as yet, actually
given in experience. They forecast possible results, things to do, not
facts (things already done). Inference is always an invasion of the
unknown, a leap from the known.</p>
<p>In this sense, a thought (what a thing suggests but is not as it is
presented) is creative,—an incursion into the novel. It involves
some inventiveness. What is suggested must, indeed, be familiar in some
context; the novelty, the inventive devising, clings to the new light in
which it is seen, the different use to which it is put. When Newton
thought of his theory of gravitation, the creative aspect of his thought
was not found in its materials. They were familiar; many of them
commonplaces—sun, moon, planets, weight, distance, mass, square of
numbers. These were not original ideas; they were established facts. His
originality lay in the use to which these familiar acquaintances were put
by introduction into an unfamiliar context. The same is true of every
striking scientific discovery, every great invention, every admirable
artistic production. Only silly folk identify creative originality with
the extraordinary and fanciful; others recognize that its measure lies in
putting everyday things to uses which had not occurred to others. The
operation is novel, not the materials out of which it is constructed.</p>
<p>The educational conclusion which follows is that all thinking is original
in a projection of considerations which have not been previously
apprehended. The child of three who discovers what can be done with
blocks, or of six who finds out what he can make by putting five cents and
five cents together, is really a discoverer, even though everybody else in
the world knows it. There is a genuine increment of experience; not
another item mechanically added on, but enrichment by a new quality. The
charm which the spontaneity of little children has for sympathetic
observers is due to perception of this intellectual originality. The joy
which children themselves experience is the joy of intellectual
constructiveness—of creativeness, if the word may be used without
misunderstanding. The educational moral I am chiefly concerned to draw is
not, however, that teachers would find their own work less of a grind and
strain if school conditions favored learning in the sense of discovery and
not in that of storing away what others pour into them; nor that it would
be possible to give even children and youth the delights of personal
intellectual productiveness—true and important as are these things.
It is that no thought, no idea, can possibly be conveyed as an idea from
one person to another. When it is told, it is, to the one to whom it is
told, another given fact, not an idea. The communication may stimulate the
other person to realize the question for himself and to think out a like
idea, or it may smother his intellectual interest and suppress his dawning
effort at thought. But what he directly gets cannot be an idea. Only by
wrestling with the conditions of the problem at first hand, seeking and
finding his own way out, does he think. When the parent or teacher has
provided the conditions which stimulate thinking and has taken a
sympathetic attitude toward the activities of the learner by entering into
a common or conjoint experience, all has been done which a second party
can do to instigate learning. The rest lies with the one directly
concerned. If he cannot devise his own solution (not of course in
isolation, but in correspondence with the teacher and other pupils) and
find his own way out he will not learn, not even if he can recite some
correct answer with one hundred per cent accuracy. We can and do supply
ready-made "ideas" by the thousand; we do not usually take much pains to
see that the one learning engages in significant situations where his own
activities generate, support, and clinch ideas—that is, perceived
meanings or connections. This does not mean that the teacher is to stand
off and look on; the alternative to furnishing ready-made subject matter
and listening to the accuracy with which it is reproduced is not
quiescence, but participation, sharing, in an activity. In such shared
activity, the teacher is a learner, and the learner is, without knowing
it, a teacher—and upon the whole, the less consciousness there is,
on either side, of either giving or receiving instruction, the better. IV.
Ideas, as we have seen, whether they be humble guesses or dignified
theories, are anticipations of possible solutions. They are anticipations
of some continuity or connection of an activity and a consequence which
has not as yet shown itself. They are therefore tested by the operation of
acting upon them. They are to guide and organize further observations,
recollections, and experiments. They are intermediate in learning, not
final. All educational reformers, as we have had occasion to remark, are
given to attacking the passivity of traditional education. They have
opposed pouring in from without, and absorbing like a sponge; they have
attacked drilling in material as into hard and resisting rock. But it is
not easy to secure conditions which will make the getting of an idea
identical with having an experience which widens and makes more precise
our contact with the environment. Activity, even self-activity, is too
easily thought of as something merely mental, cooped up within the head,
or finding expression only through the vocal organs.</p>
<p>While the need of application of ideas gained in study is acknowledged by
all the more successful methods of instruction, the exercises in
application are sometimes treated as devices for fixing what has already
been learned and for getting greater practical skill in its manipulation.
These results are genuine and not to be despised. But practice in applying
what has been gained in study ought primarily to have an intellectual
quality. As we have already seen, thoughts just as thoughts are
incomplete. At best they are tentative; they are suggestions, indications.
They are standpoints and methods for dealing with situations of
experience. Till they are applied in these situations they lack full point
and reality. Only application tests them, and only testing confers full
meaning and a sense of their reality. Short of use made of them, they tend
to segregate into a peculiar world of their own. It may be seriously
questioned whether the philosophies (to which reference has been made in
section 2 of chapter X) which isolate mind and set it over against the
world did not have their origin in the fact that the reflective or
theoretical class of men elaborated a large stock of ideas which social
conditions did not allow them to act upon and test. Consequently men were
thrown back into their own thoughts as ends in themselves.</p>
<p>However this may be, there can be no doubt that a peculiar artificiality
attaches to much of what is learned in schools. It can hardly be said that
many students consciously think of the subject matter as unreal; but it
assuredly does not possess for them the kind of reality which the subject
matter of their vital experiences possesses. They learn not to expect that
sort of reality of it; they become habituated to treating it as having
reality for the purposes of recitations, lessons, and examinations. That
it should remain inert for the experiences of daily life is more or less a
matter of course. The bad effects are twofold. Ordinary experience does
not receive the enrichment which it should; it is not fertilized by school
learning. And the attitudes which spring from getting used to and
accepting half-understood and ill-digested material weaken vigor and
efficiency of thought.</p>
<p>If we have dwelt especially on the negative side, it is for the sake of
suggesting positive measures adapted to the effectual development of
thought. Where schools are equipped with laboratories, shops, and gardens,
where dramatizations, plays, and games are freely used, opportunities
exist for reproducing situations of life, and for acquiring and applying
information and ideas in the carrying forward of progressive experiences.
Ideas are not segregated, they do not form an isolated island. They
animate and enrich the ordinary course of life. Information is vitalized
by its function; by the place it occupies in direction of action. The
phrase "opportunities exist" is used purposely. They may not be taken
advantage of; it is possible to employ manual and constructive activities
in a physical way, as means of getting just bodily skill; or they may be
used almost exclusively for "utilitarian," i.e., pecuniary, ends. But the
disposition on the part of upholders of "cultural" education to assume
that such activities are merely physical or professional in quality, is
itself a product of the philosophies which isolate mind from direction of
the course of experience and hence from action upon and with things. When
the "mental" is regarded as a self-contained separate realm, a counterpart
fate befalls bodily activity and movements. They are regarded as at the
best mere external annexes to mind. They may be necessary for the
satisfaction of bodily needs and the attainment of external decency and
comfort, but they do not occupy a necessary place in mind nor enact an
indispensable role in the completion of thought. Hence they have no place
in a liberal education—i.e., one which is concerned with the
interests of intelligence. If they come in at all, it is as a concession
to the material needs of the masses. That they should be allowed to invade
the education of the elite is unspeakable. This conclusion follows
irresistibly from the isolated conception of mind, but by the same logic
it disappears when we perceive what mind really is—namely, the
purposive and directive factor in the development of experience. While it
is desirable that all educational institutions should be equipped so as to
give students an opportunity for acquiring and testing ideas and
information in active pursuits typifying important social situations, it
will, doubtless, be a long time before all of them are thus furnished. But
this state of affairs does not afford instructors an excuse for folding
their hands and persisting in methods which segregate school knowledge.
Every recitation in every subject gives an opportunity for establishing
cross connections between the subject matter of the lesson and the wider
and more direct experiences of everyday life. Classroom instruction falls
into three kinds. The least desirable treats each lesson as an independent
whole. It does not put upon the student the responsibility of finding
points of contact between it and other lessons in the same subject, or
other subjects of study. Wiser teachers see to it that the student is
systematically led to utilize his earlier lessons to help understand the
present one, and also to use the present to throw additional light upon
what has already been acquired. Results are better, but school subject
matter is still isolated. Save by accident, out-of-school experience is
left in its crude and comparatively irreflective state. It is not subject
to the refining and expanding influences of the more accurate and
comprehensive material of direct instruction. The latter is not motivated
and impregnated with a sense of reality by being intermingled with the
realities of everyday life. The best type of teaching bears in mind the
desirability of affecting this interconnection. It puts the student in the
habitual attitude of finding points of contact and mutual bearings.</p>
<p><SPAN name="link2H_SUMM12" id="link2H_SUMM12"></SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> Summary. Processes of instruction are unified in the degree in which </h2>
<p>they center in the production of good habits of thinking. While we may
speak, without error, of the method of thought, the important thing is
that thinking is the method of an educative experience. The essentials of
method are therefore identical with the essentials of reflection. They are
first that the pupil have a genuine situation of experience—that
there be a continuous activity in which he is interested for its own sake;
secondly, that a genuine problem develop within this situation as a
stimulus to thought; third, that he possess the information and make the
observations needed to deal with it; fourth, that suggested solutions
occur to him which he shall be responsible for developing in an orderly
way; fifth, that he have opportunity and occasion to test his ideas by
application, to make their meaning clear and to discover for himself their
validity.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />