<h2>PART II. Of the Expense of Justice</h2>
<p>The second duty of the sovereign, that of protecting, as far as possible,
every member of the society from the injustice or oppression of every
other member of it, or the duty of establishing an exact administration of
justice, requires two very different degrees of expense in the different
periods of society.</p>
<p>Among nations of hunters, as there is scarce any property, or at least
none that exceeds the value of two or three days labour; so there is
seldom any established magistrate, or any regular administration of
justice. Men who have no property, can injure one another only in their
persons or reputations. But when one man kills, wounds, beats, or defames
another, though he to whom the injury is done suffers, he who does it
receives no benefit. It is otherwise with the injuries to property. The
benefit of the person who does the injury is often equal to the loss of
him who suffers it. Envy, malice, or resentment, are the only passions
which can prompt one man to injure another in his person or reputation.
But the greater part of men are not very frequently under the influence of
those passions; and the very worst men are so only occasionally. As their
gratification, too, how agreeable soever it may be to certain characters,
is not attended with any real or permanent advantage, it is, in the
greater part of men, commonly restrained by prudential considerations. Men
may live together in society with some tolerable degree of security,
though there is no civil magistrate to protect them from the injustice of
those passions. But avarice and ambition in the rich, in the poor the
hatred of labour and the love of present ease and enjoyment, are the
passions which prompt to invade property; passions much more steady in
their operation, and much more universal in their influence. Wherever
there is a great property, there is great inequality. For one very rich
man, there must be at least five hundred poor, and the affluence of the
few supposes the indigence of the many. The affluence of the rich excites
the indignation of the poor, who are often both driven by want, and
prompted by envy to invade his possessions. It is only under the shelter
of the civil magistrate, that the owner of that valuable property, which
is acquired by the labour of many years, or perhaps of many successive
generations, can sleep a single night in security. He is at all times
surrounded by unknown enemies, whom, though he never provoked, he can
never appease, and from whose injustice he can be protected only by the
powerful arm of the civil magistrate, continually held up to chastise it.
The acquisition of valuable and extensive property, therefore, necessarily
requires the establishment of civil government. Where there is no
property, or at least none that exceeds the value of two or three days
labour, civil government is not so necessary.</p>
<p>Civil government supposes a certain subordination. But as the necessity of
civil government gradually grows up with the acquisition of valuable
property; so the principal causes, which naturally introduce
subordination, gradually grow up with the growth of that valuable
property.</p>
<p>The causes or circumstances which naturally introduce subordination, or
which naturally and antecedent to any civil institution, give some men
some superiority over the greater part of their brethren, seem to be four
in number.</p>
<p>The first of those causes or circumstances, is the superiority of personal
qualifications, of strength, beauty, and agility of body; of wisdom and
virtue; of prudence, justice, fortitude, and moderation of mind. The
qualifications of the body, unless supported by those of the mind, can
give little authority in any period of society. He is a very strong man,
who, by mere strength of body, can force two weak ones to obey him. The
qualifications of the mind can alone give very great authority. They are
however, invisible qualities; always disputable, and generally disputed.
No society, whether barbarous or civilized, has ever found it convenient
to settle the rules of precedency of rank and subordination, according to
those invisible qualities; but according to something that is more plain
and palpable.</p>
<p>The second of those causes or circumstances, is the superiority of age. An
old man, provided his age is not so far advanced as to give suspicion of
dotage, is everywhere more respected than a young man of equal rank,
fortune, and abilities. Among nations of hunters, such as the native
tribes of North America, age is the sole foundation of rank and
precedency. Among them, father is the appellation of a superior; brother,
of an equal; and son, of an inferior. In the most opulent and civilized
nations, age regulates rank among those who are in every other respect
equal; and among whom, therefore, there is nothing else to regulate it.
Among brothers and among sisters, the eldest always takes place; and in
the succession of the paternal estate, every thing which cannot be
divided, but must go entire to one person, such as a title of honour, is
in most cases given to the eldest. Age is a plain and palpable quality,
which admits of no dispute.</p>
<p>The third of those causes or circumstances, is the superiority of fortune.
The authority of riches, however, though great in every age of society,
is, perhaps, greatest in the rudest ages of society, which admits of any
considerable inequality of fortune. A Tartar chief, the increase of whose
flocks and herds is sufficient to maintain a thousand men, cannot well
employ that increase in any other way than in maintaining a thousand men.
The rude state of his society does not afford him any manufactured produce
any trinkets or baubles of any kind, for which he can exchange that part
of his rude produce which is over and above his own consumption. The
thousand men whom he thus maintains, depending entirely upon him for their
subsistence, must both obey his orders in war, and submit to his
jurisdiction in peace. He is necessarily both their general and their
judge, and his chieftainship is the necessary effect of the superiority of
his fortune. In an opulent and civilized society, a man may possess a much
greater fortune, and yet not be able to command a dozen of people. Though
the produce of his estate may be sufficient to maintain, and may, perhaps,
actually maintain, more than a thousand people, yet, as those people pay
for every thing which they get from him, as he gives scarce any thing to
any body but in exchange for an equivalent, there is scarce anybody who
considers himself as entirely dependent upon him, and his authority
extends only over a few menial servants. The authority of fortune,
however, is very great, even in an opulent and civilized society. That it
is much greater than that either of age or of personal qualities, has been
the constant complaint of every period of society which admitted of any
considerable inequality of fortune. The first period of society, that of
hunters, admits of no such inequality. Universal poverty establishes their
universal equality; and the superiority, either of age or of personal
qualities, are the feeble, but the sole foundations of authority and
subordination. There is, therefore, little or no authority or
subordination in this period of society. The second period of society,
that of shepherds, admits of very great inequalities of fortune, and there
is no period in which the superiority of fortune gives so great authority
to those who possess it. There is no period, accordingly, in which
authority and subordination are more perfectly established. The authority
of an Arabian scherif is very great; that of a Tartar khan altogether
despotical.</p>
<p>The fourth of those causes or circumstances, is the superiority of birth.
Superiority of birth supposes an ancient superiority of fortune in the
family of the person who claims it. All families are equally ancient; and
the ancestors of the prince, though they may be better known, cannot well
be more numerous than those of the beggar. Antiquity of family means
everywhere the antiquity either of wealth, or of that greatness which is
commonly either founded upon wealth, or accompanied with it. Upstart
greatness is everywhere less respected than ancient greatness. The hatred
of usurpers, the love of the family of an ancient monarch, are in a great
measure founded upon the contempt which men naturally have for the former,
and upon their veneration for the latter. As a military officer submits,
without reluctance, to the authority of a superior by whom he has always
been commanded, but cannot bear that his inferior should be set over his
head; so men easily submit to a family to whom they and their ancestors
have always submitted; but are fired with indignation when another family,
in whom they had never acknowledged any such superiority, assumes a
dominion over them.</p>
<p>The distinction of birth, being subsequent to the inequality of fortune,
can have no place in nations of hunters, among whom all men, being equal
in fortune, must likewise be very nearly equal in birth. The son of a wise
and brave man may, indeed, even among them, be somewhat more respected
than a man of equal merit, who has the misfortune to be the son of a fool
or a coward. The difference, however will not be very great; and there
never was, I believe, a great family in the world, whose illustration was
entirely derived from the inheritance of wisdom and virtue.</p>
<p>The distinction of birth not only may, but always does, take place among
nations of shepherds. Such nations are always strangers to every sort of
luxury, and great wealth can scarce ever be dissipated among them by
improvident profusion. There are no nations, accordingly, who abound more
in families revered and honoured on account of their descent from a long
race of great and illustrious ancestors; because there are no nations
among whom wealth is likely to continue longer in the same families.</p>
<p>Birth and fortune are evidently the two circumstances which principally
set one man above another. They are the two great sources of personal
distinction, and are, therefore, the principal causes which naturally
establish authority and subordination among men. Among nations of
shepherds, both those causes operate with their full force. The great
shepherd or herdsman, respected on account of his great wealth, and of the
great number of those who depend upon him for subsistence, and revered on
account of the nobleness of his birth, and of the immemorial antiquity or
his illustrious family, has a natural authority over all the inferior
shepherds or herdsmen of his horde or clan. He can command the united
force of a greater number of people than any of them. His military power
is greater than that of any of them. In time of war, they are all of them
naturally disposed to muster themselves under his banner, rather than
under that of any other person; and his birth and fortune thus naturally
procure to him some sort of executive power. By commanding, too, the
united force of a greater number of people than any of them, he is best
able to compel any one of them, who may have injured another, to
compensate the wrong. He is the person, therefore, to whom all those who
are too weak to defend themselves naturally look up for protection. It is
to him that they naturally complain of the injuries which they imagine
have been done to them; and his interposition, in such cases, is more
easily submitted to, even by the person complained of, than that of any
other person would be. His birth and fortune thus naturally procure him
some sort of judicial authority.</p>
<p>It is in the age of shepherds, in the second period of society, that the
inequality of fortune first begins to take place, and introduces among men
a degree of authority and subordination, which could not possibly exist
before. It thereby introduces some degree of that civil government which
is indispensably necessary for its own preservation; and it seems to do
this naturally, and even independent of the consideration of that
necessity. The consideration of that necessity comes, no doubt,
afterwards, to contribute very much to maintain and secure that authority
and subordination. The rich, in particular, are necessarily interested to
support that order of things, which can alone secure them in the
possession of their own advantages. Men of inferior wealth combine to
defend those of superior wealth in the possession of their property, in
order that men of superior wealth may combine to defend them in the
possession of theirs. All the inferior shepherds and herdsmen feel, that
the security of their own herds and flocks depends upon the security of
those of the great shepherd or herdsman; that the maintenance of their
lesser authority depends upon that of his greater authority; and that upon
their subordination to him depends his power of keeping their inferiors in
subordination to them. They constitute a sort of little nobility, who feel
themselves interested to defend the property, and to support the
authority, of their own little sovereign, in order that he may be able to
defend their property, and to support their authority. Civil government,
so far as it is instituted for the security of property, is, in reality,
instituted for the defence of the rich against the poor, or of those who
have some property against those who have none at all.</p>
<p>The judicial authority of such a sovereign, however, far from being a
cause of expense, was, for a long time, a source of revenue to him. The
persons who applied to him for justice were always willing to pay for it,
and a present never failed to accompany a petition. After the authority of
the sovereign, too, was thoroughly established, the person found guilty,
over and above the satisfaction which he was obliged to make to the party,
was like-wise forced to pay an amercement to the sovereign. He had given
trouble, he had disturbed, he had broke the peace of his lord the king,
and for those offences an amercement was thought due. In the Tartar
governments of Asia, in the governments of Europe which were founded by
the German and Scythian nations who overturned the Roman empire, the
administration of justice was a considerable source of revenue, both to
the sovereign, and to all the lesser chiefs or lords who exercised under
him any particular jurisdiction, either over some particular tribe or
clan, or over some particular territory or district. Originally, both the
sovereign and the inferior chiefs used to exercise this jurisdiction in
their own persons. Afterwards, they universally found it convenient to
delegate it to some substitute, bailiff, or judge. This substitute,
however, was still obliged to account to his principal or constituent for
the profits of the jurisdiction. Whoever reads the instructions (They are
to be found in Tyrol's History of England) which were given to the judges
of the circuit in the time of Henry II will see clearly that those judges
were a sort of itinerant factors, sent round the country for the purpose
of levying certain branches of the king's revenue. In those days, the
administration of justice not only afforded a certain revenue to the
sovereign, but, to procure this revenue, seems to have been one of the
principal advantages which he proposed to obtain by the administration of
justice.</p>
<p>This scheme of making the administration of justice subservient to the
purposes of revenue, could scarce fail to be productive of several very
gross abuses. The person who applied for justice with a large present in
his hand, was likely to get something more than justice; while he who
applied for it with a small one was likely to get something less. Justice,
too, might frequently be delayed, in order that this present might be
repeated. The amercement, besides, of the person complained of, might
frequently suggest a very strong reason for finding him in the wrong, even
when he had not really been so. That such abuses were far from being
uncommon, the ancient history of every country in Europe bears witness.</p>
<p>When the sovereign or chief exercises his judicial authority in his own
person, how much soever he might abuse it, it must have been scarce
possible to get any redress; because there could seldom be any body
powerful enough to call him to account. When he exercised it by a bailiff,
indeed, redress might sometimes be had. If it was for his own benefit
only, that the bailiff had been guilty of an act of injustice, the
sovereign himself might not always be unwilling to punish him, or to
oblige him to repair the wrong. But if it was for the benefit of his
sovereign; if it was in order to make court to the person who appointed
him, and who might prefer him, that he had committed any act of
oppression; redress would, upon most occasions, be as impossible as if the
sovereign had committed it himself. In all barbarous governments,
accordingly, in all those ancient governments of Europe in particular,
which were founded upon the ruins of the Roman empire, the administration
of justice appears for a long time to have been extremely corrupt; far
from being quite equal and impartial, even under the best monarchs, and
altogether profligate under the worst.</p>
<p>Among nations of shepherds, where the sovereign or chief is only the
greatest shepherd or herdsman of the horde or clan, he is maintained in
the same manner as any of his vassals or subjects, by the increase of his
own herds or flocks. Among those nations of husbandmen, who are but just
come out of the shepherd state, and who are not much advanced beyond that
state, such as the Greek tribes appear to have been about the time of the
Trojan war, and our German and Scythian ancestors, when they first settled
upon the ruins of the western empire; the sovereign or chief is, in the
same manner, only the greatest landlord of the country, and is maintained
in the same manner as any other landlord, by a revenue derived from his
own private estate, or from what, in modern Europe, was called the demesne
of the crown. His subjects, upon ordinary occasions, contribute nothing to
his support, except when, in order to protect them from the oppression of
some of their fellow-subjects, they stand in need of his authority. The
presents which they make him upon such occasions constitute the whole
ordinary revenue, the whole of the emoluments which, except, perhaps, upon
some very extraordinary emergencies, he derives from his dominion over
them. When Agamemnon, in Homer, offers to Achilles, for his friendship,
the sovereignty of seven Greek cities, the sole advantage which he
mentions as likely to be derived from it was, that the people would honour
him with presents. As long as such presents, as long as the emoluments of
justice, or what may be called the fees of court, constituted, in this
manner, the whole ordinary revenue which the sovereign derived from his
sovereignty, it could not well be expected, it could not even decently be
proposed, that he should give them up altogether. It might, and it
frequently was proposed, that he should regulate and ascertain them. But
after they had been so regulated and ascertained, how to hinder a person
who was all-powerful from extending them beyond those regulations, was
still very difficult, not to say impossible. During the continuance of
this state of things, therefore, the corruption of justice, naturally
resulting from the arbitrary and uncertain nature of those presents,
scarce admitted of any effectual remedy.</p>
<p>But when, from different causes, chiefly from the continually increasing
expense of defending the nation against the invasion of other nations, the
private estate of the sovereign had become altogether insufficient for
defraying the expense of the sovereignty; and when it had become necessary
that the people should, for their own security, contribute towards this
expense by taxes of different kinds; it seems to have been very commonly
stipulated, that no present for the administration of justice should,
under any pretence, be accepted either by the sovereign, or by his
bailiffs and substitutes, the judges. Those presents, it seems to have
been supposed, could more easily be abolished altogether, than effectually
regulated and ascertained. Fixed salaries were appointed to the judges,
which were supposed to compensate to them the loss of whatever might have
been their share of the ancient emoluments of justice; as the taxes more
than compensated to the sovereign the loss of his. Justice was then said
to be administered gratis.</p>
<p>Justice, however, never was in reality administered gratis in any country.
Lawyers and attorneys, at least, must always be paid by the parties; and
if they were not, they would perform their duty still worse than they
actually perform it. The fees annually paid to lawyers and attorneys,
amount, in every court, to a much greater sum than the salaries of the
judges. The circumstance of those salaries being paid by the crown, can
nowhere much diminish the necessary expense of a law-suit. But it was not
so much to diminish the expense, as to prevent the corruption of justice,
that the judges were prohibited from receiving my present or fee from the
parties.</p>
<p>The office of judge is in itself so very honourable, that men are willing
to accept of it, though accompanied with very small emoluments. The
inferior office of justice of peace, though attended with a good deal of
trouble, and in most cases with no emoluments at all, is an object of
ambition to the greater part of our country gentlemen. The salaries of all
the different judges, high and low, together with the whole expense of the
administration and execution of justice, even where it is not managed with
very good economy, makes, in any civilized country, but a very
inconsiderable part of the whole expense of government.</p>
<p>The whole expense of justice, too, might easily be defrayed by the fees of
court; and, without exposing the administration of justice to any real
hazard of corruption, the public revenue might thus be entirely discharged
from a certain, though perhaps but a small incumbrance. It is difficult to
regulate the fees of court effectually, where a person so powerful as the
sovereign is to share in them and to derive any considerable part of his
revenue from them. It is very easy, where the judge is the principal
person who can reap any benefit from them. The law can very easily oblige
the judge to respect the regulation though it might not always be able to
make the sovereign respect it. Where the fees of court are precisely
regulated and ascertained where they are paid all at once, at a certain
period of every process, into the hands of a cashier or receiver, to be by
him distributed in certain known proportions among the different judges
after the process is decided and not till it is decided; there seems to be
no more danger of corruption than when such fees are prohibited
altogether. Those fees, without occasioning any considerable increase in
the expense of a law-suit, might be rendered fully sufficient for
defraying the whole expense of justice. But not being paid to the judges
till the process was determined, they might be some incitement to the
diligence of the court in examining and deciding it. In courts which
consisted of a considerable number of judges, by proportioning the share
of each judge to the number of hours and days which he had employed in
examining the process, either in the court, or in a committee, by order of
the court, those fees might give some encouragement to the diligence of
each particular judge. Public services are never better performed, than
when their reward comes only in consequence of their being performed, and
is proportioned to the diligence employed in performing them. In the
different parliaments of France, the fees of court (called epices and
vacations) constitute the far greater part of the emoluments of the
judges. After all deductions are made, the neat salary paid by the crown
to a counsellor or judge in the parliament of Thoulouse, in rank and
dignity the second parliament of the kingdom, amounts only to 150 livres,
about �6:11s. sterling a-year. About seven years ago, that sum was in the
same place the ordinary yearly wages of a common footman. The distribution
of these epices, too, is according to the diligence of the judges. A
diligent judge gains a comfortable, though moderate revenue, by his
office; an idle one gets little more than his salary. Those parliaments
are, perhaps, in many respects, not very convenient courts of justice; but
they have never been accused; they seem never even to have been suspected
of corruption.</p>
<p>The fees of court seem originally to have been the principal support of
the different courts of justice in England. Each court endeavoured to draw
to itself as much business as it could, and was, upon that account,
willing to take cognizance of many suits which were not originally
intended to fall under its jurisdiction. The court of king's bench,
instituted for the trial of criminal causes only, took cognizance of civil
suits; the plaintiff pretending that the defendant, in not doing him
justice, had been guilty of some trespass or misdemeanour. The court of
exchequer, instituted for the levying of the king's revenue, and for
enforcing the payment of such debts only as were due to the king, took
cognizance of all other contract debts; the planitiff alleging that he
could not pay the king, because the defendant would not pay him. In
consequence of such fictions, it came, in many cases, to depend altogether
upon the parties, before what court they would choose to have their cause
tried, and each court endeavoured, by superior dispatch and impartiality,
to draw to itself as many causes as it could. The present admirable
constitution of the courts of justice in England was, perhaps, originally,
in a great measure, formed by this emulation, which anciently took place
between their respective judges: each judge endeavouring to give, in his
own court, the speediest and most effectual remedy which the law would
admit, for every sort of injustice. Originally, the courts of law gave
damages only for breach of contract. The court of chancery, as a court of
conscience, first took upon it to enforce the specific performance of
agreements. When the breach of contract consisted in the non-payment of
money, the damage sustained could be compensated in no other way than by
ordering payment, which was equivalent to a specific performance of the
agreement. In such cases, therefore, the remedy of the courts of law was
sufficient. It was not so in others. When the tenant sued his lord for
having unjustly outed him of his lease, the damages which he recovered
were by no means equivalent to the possession of the land. Such causes,
therefore, for some time, went all to the court of chancery, to the no
small loss of the courts of law. It was to draw back such causes to
themselves, that the courts of law are said to have invented the
artificial and fictitious writ of ejectment, the most effectual remedy for
an unjust outer or dispossession of land.</p>
<p>A stamp-duty upon the law proceedings of each particular court, to be
levied by that court, and applied towards the maintenance of the judges,
and other officers belonging to it, might in the same manner, afford a
revenue sufficient for defraying the expense of the administration of
justice, without bringing any burden upon the general revenue of the
society. The judges, indeed, might in this case, be under the temptation
of multiplying unnecessarily the proceedings upon every cause, in order to
increase, as much as possible, the produce of such a stamp-duty. It has
been the custom in modern Europe to regulate, upon most occasions, the
payment of the attorneys and clerks of court according to the number of
pages which they had occasion to write; the court, however, requiring that
each page should contain so many lines, and each line so many words. In
order to increase their payment, the attorneys and clerks have contrived
to multiply words beyond all necessity, to the corruption of the law
language of, I believe, every court of justice in Europe. A like
temptation might, perhaps, occasion a like corruption in the form of law
proceedings.</p>
<p>But whether the administration of justice be so contrived as to defray its
own expense, or whether the judges be maintained by fixed salaries paid to
them from some other fund, it does not seen necessary that the person or
persons entrusted with the executive power should be charged with the
management of that fund, or with the payment of those salaries. That fund
might arise from the rent of landed estates, the management of each estate
being entrusted to the particular court which was to be maintained by it.
That fund might arise even from the interest of a sum of money, the
lending out of which might, in the same manner, be entrusted to the court
which was to be maintained by it. A part, though indeed but a small part
of the salary of the judges of the court of session in Scotland, arises
from the interest of a sum of money. The necessary instability of such a
fund seems, however, to render it an improper one for the maintenance of
an institution which ought to last for ever.</p>
<p>The separation of the judicial from the executive power, seems originally
to have arisen from the increasing business of the society, in consequence
of its increasing improvement. The administration of justice became so
laborious and so complicated a duty, as to require the undivided attention
of the person to whom it was entrusted. The person entrusted with the
executive power, not having leisure to attend to the decision of private
causes himself, a deputy was appointed to decide them in his stead. In the
progress of the Roman greatness, the consul was too much occupied with the
political affairs of the state, to attend to the administration of
justice. A praetor, therefore, was appointed to administer it in his
stead. In the progress of the European monarchies, which were founded upon
the ruins of the Roman empire, the sovereigns and the great lords came
universally to consider the administration of justice as an office both
too laborious and too ignoble for them to execute in their own persons.
They universally, therefore, discharged themselves of it, by appointing a
deputy, bailiff or judge.</p>
<p>When the judicial is united to the executive power, it is scarce possible
that justice should not frequently be sacrificed to what is vulgarly
called politics. The persons entrusted with the great interests of the
state may even without any corrupt views, sometimes imagine it necessary
to sacrifice to those interests the rights of a private man. But upon the
impartial administration of justice depends the liberty of every
individual, the sense which he has of his own security. In order to make
every individual feel himself perfectly secure in the possession of every
right which belongs to him, it is not only necessary that the judicial
should be separated from the executive power, but that it should be
rendered as much as possible independent of that power. The judge should
not be liable to be removed from his office according to the caprice of
that power. The regular payment of his salary should not depend upon the
good will, or even upon the good economy of that power.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />