<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0043" id="link2H_4_0043"></SPAN></p>
<h2> SECT. VI. OF PERSONAL IDENTITY </h2>
<p>There are some philosophers who imagine we are every moment intimately
conscious of what we call our SELF; that we feel its existence and its
continuance in existence; and are certain, beyond the evidence of a
demonstration, both o its perfect identity and simplicity. The strongest
sensation, the most violent passion, say they, instead of distracting us
from this view, only fix it the more intensely, and make us consider their
influence on self either by their pain or pleasure. To attempt a farther
proof of this were to weaken its evidence; since no proof can be derived
from any fact, of which we are so intimately conscious; nor is there any
thing, of which we can be certain, if we doubt of this.</p>
<p>Unluckily all these positive assertions are contrary to that very
experience, which is pleaded for them, nor have we any idea of self, after
the manner it is here explained. For from what impression coued this idea
be derived? This question it is impossible to answer without a manifest
contradiction and absurdity; and yet it is a question, which must
necessarily be answered, if we would have the idea of self pass for clear
and intelligible, It must be some one impression, that gives rise to every
real idea. But self or person is not any one impression, but that to which
our several impressions and ideas are supposed to have a reference. If any
impression gives rise to the idea of self, that impression must continue
invariably the same, through the whole course of our lives; since self is
supposed to exist after that manner. But there is no impression constant
and invariable. Pain and pleasure, grief and joy, passions and sensations
succeed each other, and never all exist at the same time. It cannot,
therefore, be from any of these impressions, or from any other, that the
idea of self is derived; and consequently there is no such idea.</p>
<p>But farther, what must become of all our particular perceptions upon this
hypothesis? All these are different, and distinguishable, and separable
from each other, and may be separately considered, and may exist
separately, and have no Deed of tiny thing to support their existence.
After what manner, therefore, do they belong to self; and how are they
connected with it? For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I
call myself, I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of
heat or cold, light or shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never
can catch myself at any time without a perception, and never can observe
any thing but the perception. When my perceptions are removed for any
time, as by sound sleep; so long am I insensible of myself, and may truly
be said not to exist. And were all my perceptions removed by death, and
coued I neither think, nor feel, nor see, nor love, nor hate after the
dissolution of my body, I should be entirely annihilated, nor do I
conceive what is farther requisite to make me a perfect non-entity. If any
one, upon serious and unprejudiced reflection thinks he has a different
notion of himself, I must confess I call reason no longer with him. All I
can allow him is, that he may be in the right as well as I, and that we
are essentially different in this particular. He may, perhaps, perceive
something simple and continued, which he calls himself; though I am
certain there is no such principle in me.</p>
<p>But setting aside some metaphysicians of this kind, I may venture to
affirm of the rest of mankind, that they are nothing but a bundle or
collection of different perceptions, which succeed each other with an
inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and movement. Our eyes
cannot turn in their sockets without varying our perceptions. Our thought
is still more variable than our sight; and all our other senses and
faculties contribute to this change; nor is there any single power of the
soul, which remains unalterably the same, perhaps for one moment. The mind
is a kind of theatre, where several perceptions successively make their
appearance; pass, re-pass, glide away, and mingle in an infinite variety
of postures and situations. There is properly no simplicity in it at one
time, nor identity in different; whatever natural propension we may have
to imagine that simplicity and identity. The comparison of the theatre
must not mislead us. They are the successive perceptions only, that
constitute the mind; nor have we the most distant notion of the place,
where these scenes are represented, or of the materials, of which it is
composed.</p>
<p>What then gives us so great a propension to ascribe an identity to these
successive perceptions, and to suppose ourselves possest of an invariable
and uninterrupted existence through the whole course of our lives? In
order to answer this question, we must distinguish betwixt personal
identity, as it regards our thought or imagination, and as it regards our
passions or the concern we take in ourselves. The first is our present
subject; and to explain it perfectly we must take the matter pretty deep,
and account for that identity, which we attribute to plants and animals;
there being a great analogy betwixt it, and the identity of a self or
person.</p>
<p>We have a distinct idea of an object, that remains invariable and
uninterrupted through a supposed variation of time; and this idea we call
that of identity or sameness. We have also a distinct idea of several
different objects existing in succession, and connected together by a
close relation; and this to an accurate view affords as perfect a notion
of diversity, as if there was no manner of relation among the objects. But
though these two ideas of identity, and a succession of related objects be
in themselves perfectly distinct, and even contrary, yet it is certain,
that in our common way of thinking they are generally confounded with each
other. That action of the imagination, by which we consider the
uninterrupted and invariable object, and that by which we reflect on the
succession of related objects, are almost the same to the feeling, nor is
there much more effort of thought required in the latter case than in the
former. The relation facilitates the transition of the mind from one
object to another, and renders its passage as smooth as if it contemplated
one continued object. This resemblance is the cause of the confusion and
mistake, and makes us substitute the notion of identity, instead of that
of related objects. However at one instant we may consider the related
succession as variable or interrupted, we are sure the next to ascribe to
it a perfect identity, and regard it as enviable and uninterrupted. Our
propensity to this mistake is so great from the resemblance
above-mentioned, that we fall into it before we are aware; and though we
incessantly correct ourselves by reflection, and return to a more accurate
method of thinking, yet we cannot long sustain our philosophy, or take off
this biass from the imagination. Our last resource is to yield to it, and
boldly assert that these different related objects are in effect the same,
however interrupted and variable. In order to justify to ourselves this
absurdity, we often feign some new and unintelligible principle, that
connects the objects together, and prevents their interruption or
variation. Thus we feign the continued existence of the perceptions of our
senses, to remove the interruption: and run into the notion of a soul, and
self, and substance, to disguise the variation. But we may farther
observe, that where we do not give rise to such a fiction, our propension
to confound identity with relation is so great, that we are apt to imagine
[FN 10] something unknown and mysterious, connecting the parts, beside
their relation; and this I take to be the case with regard to the identity
we ascribe to plants and vegetables. And even when this does not take
place, we still feel a propensity to confound these ideas, though we a-re
not able fully to satisfy ourselves in that particular, nor find any thing
invariable and uninterrupted to justify our notion of identity.</p>
<p>[FN 10 If the reader is desirous to see how a great<br/>
genius may be influencd by these seemingly trivial<br/>
principles of the imagination, as well as the mere vulgar,<br/>
let him read my Lord SHAFTSBURYS reasonings concerning the<br/>
uniting principle of the universe, and the identity of<br/>
plants and animals. See his MORALISTS: or, PHILOSOPHICAL<br/>
RHAPSODY.]<br/></p>
<p>Thus the controversy concerning identity is not merely a dispute of words.
For when we attribute identity, in an improper sense, to variable or
interrupted objects, our mistake is not confined to the expression, but is
commonly attended with a fiction, either of something invariable and
uninterrupted, or of something mysterious and inexplicable, or at least
with a propensity to such fictions. What will suffice to prove this
hypothesis to the satisfaction of every fair enquirer, is to shew from
daily experience and observation, that the objects, which are variable or
interrupted, and yet are supposed to continue the same, are such only as
consist of a succession of parts, connected together by resemblance,
contiguity, or causation. For as such a succession answers evidently to
our notion of diversity, it can only be by mistake we ascribe to it an
identity; and as the relation of parts, which leads us into this mistake,
is really nothing but a quality, which produces an association of ideas,
and an easy transition of the imagination from one to another, it can only
be from the resemblance, which this act of the mind bears to that, by
which we contemplate one continued object, that the error arises. Our
chief business, then, must be to prove, that all objects, to which we
ascribe identity, without observing their invariableness and
uninterruptedness, are such as consist of a succession of related objects.</p>
<p>In order to this, suppose any mass of matter, of which the parts are
contiguous and connected, to be placed before us; it is plain we must
attribute a perfect identity to this mass, provided all the parts continue
uninterruptedly and invariably the same, whatever motion or change of
place we may observe either in the whole or in any of the parts. But
supposing some very small or inconsiderable part to be added to the mass,
or subtracted from it; though this absolutely destroys the identity of the
whole, strictly speaking; yet as we seldom think so accurately, we scruple
not to pronounce a mass of matter the same, where we find so trivial an
alteration. The passage of the thought from the object before the change
to the object after it, is so smooth and easy, that we scarce perceive the
transition, and are apt to imagine, that it is nothing but a continued
survey of the same object.</p>
<p>There is a very remarkable circumstance, that attends this experiment;
which is, that though the change of any considerable part in a mass of
matter destroys the identity of the whole, let we must measure the
greatness of the part, not absolutely, but by its proportion to the whole.
The addition or diminution of a mountain would not be sufficient to
produce a diversity in a planet: though the change of a very few inches
would be able to destroy the identity of some bodies. It will be
impossible to account for this, but by reflecting that objects operate
upon the mind, and break or interrupt the continuity of its actions not
according to their real greatness, but according to their proportion to
each other: And therefore, since this interruption makes an object cease
to appear the same, it must be the uninterrupted progress o the thought,
which constitutes the imperfect identity.</p>
<p>This may be confirmed by another phenomenon. A change in any considerable
part of a body destroys its identity; but it is remarkable, that where the
change is produced gradually and insensibly we are less apt to ascribe to
it the same effect. The reason can plainly be no other, than that the
mind, in following the successive changes of the body, feels an easy
passage from the surveying its condition in one moment to the viewing of
it in another, and at no particular time perceives any interruption in its
actions. From which continued perception, it ascribes a continued
existence and identity to the object.</p>
<p>But whatever precaution we may use in introducing the changes gradually,
and making them proportionable to the whole, it is certain, that where the
changes are at last observed to become considerable, we make a scruple of
ascribing identity to such different objects. There is, however, another
artifice, by which we may induce the imagination to advance a step
farther; and that is, by producing a reference of the parts to each other,
and a combination to some common end or purpose. A ship, of which a
considerable part has been changed by frequent reparations, is still
considered as the same; nor does the difference of the materials hinder us
from ascribing an identity to it. The common end, in which the parts
conspire, is the same under all their variations, and affords an easy
transition of the imagination from one situation of the body to another.</p>
<p>But this is still more remarkable, when we add a sympathy of parts to
their common end, and suppose that they bear to each other, the reciprocal
relation of cause and effect in all their actions and operations. This is
the case with all animals and vegetables; where not only the several parts
have a reference to some general purpose, but also a mutual dependence on,
and connexion with each other. The effect of so strong a relation is, that
though every one must allow, that in a very few years both vegetables and
animals endure a total change, yet we still attribute identity to them,
while their form, size, and substance are entirely altered. An oak, that
grows from a small plant to a large tree, is still the same oak; though
there be not one particle of matter, or figure of its parts the same. An
infant becomes a man-, and is sometimes fat, sometimes lean, without any
change in his identity.</p>
<p>We may also consider the two following phaenomena, which are remarkable in
their kind. The first is, that though we commonly be able to distinguish
pretty exactly betwixt numerical and specific identity, yet it sometimes
happens, that we confound them, and in our thinking and reasoning employ
the one for the other. Thus a man, who bears a noise, that is frequently
interrupted and renewed, says, it is still the same noise; though it is
evident the sounds have only a specific identity or resemblance, and there
is nothing numerically the same, but the cause, which produced them. In
like manner it may be said without breach of the propriety of language,
that such a church, which was formerly of brick, fell to ruin, and that
the parish rebuilt the same church of free-stone, and according to modern
architecture. Here neither the form nor materials are the same, nor is
there any thing common to the two objects, but their relation to the
inhabitants of the parish; and yet this alone is sufficient to make us
denominate them the same. But we must observe, that in these cases the
first object is in a manner annihilated before the second comes into
existence; by which means, we are never presented in any one point of time
with the idea of difference and multiplicity: and for that reason are less
scrupulous in calling them the same.</p>
<p>Secondly, We may remark, that though in a succession of related objects,
it be in a manner requisite, that the change of parts be not sudden nor
entire, in order to preserve the identity, yet where the objects are in
their nature changeable and inconstant, we admit of a more sudden
transition, than would otherwise be consistent with that relation. Thus as
the nature of a river consists in the motion and change of parts; though
in less than four and twenty hours these be totally altered; this hinders
not the river from continuing the same during several ages. What is
natural and essential to any thing is, in a manner, expected; and what is
expected makes less impression, and appears of less moment, than what is
unusual and extraordinary. A considerable change of the former kind seems
really less to the imagination, than the most trivial alteration of the
latter; and by breaking less the continuity of the thought, has less
influence in destroying the identity.</p>
<p>We now proceed to explain the nature of personal identity, which has
become so great a question ill philosophy, especially of late years in
England, where all the abstruser sciences are studyed with a peculiar
ardour and application. And here it is evident, the same method of
reasoning must be continued which has so successfully explained the
identity of plants, and animals, and ships, and houses, and of all the
compounded and changeable productions either of art or nature. The
identity, which we ascribe to the mind of man, is only a fictitious one,
and of a like kind with that which we ascribe to vegetables and animal
bodies. It cannot, therefore, have a different origin, but must proceed
from a like operation of the imagination upon like objects.</p>
<p>But lest this argument should not convince the reader; though in my
opinion perfectly decisive; let him weigh the following reasoning, which
is still closer and more immediate. It is evident, that the identity,
which we attribute to the human mind, however perfect we may imagine it to
be, is not able to run the several different perceptions into one, and
make them lose their characters of distinction and difference, which are
essential to them. It is still true, that every distinct perception, which
enters into the composition of the mind, is a distinct existence, and is
different, and distinguishable, and separable from every other perception,
either contemporary or successive. But, as, notwithstanding this
distinction and separability, we suppose the whole train of perceptions to
be united by identity, a question naturally arises concerning this
relation of identity; whether it be something that really binds our
several perceptions together, or only associates their ideas in the
imagination. That is, in other words, whether in pronouncing concerning
the identity of a person, we observe some real bond among his perceptions,
or only feel one among the ideas we form of them. This question we might
easily decide, if we would recollect what has been already proud at large,
that the understanding never observes any real connexion among objects,
and that even the union of cause and effect, when strictly examined,
resolves itself into a customary association of ideas. For from thence it
evidently follows, that identity is nothing really belonging to these
different perceptions, and uniting them together; but is merely a quality,
which we attribute to them, because of the union of their ideas in the
imagination, when we reflect upon them. Now the only qualities, which can
give ideas an union in the imagination, are these three relations
above-mentioned. There are the uniting principles in the ideal world, and
without them every distinct object is separable by the mind, and may be
separately considered, and appears not to have any more connexion with any
other object, than if disjoined by the greatest difference and remoteness.
It is, therefore, on some of these three relations of resemblance,
contiguity and causation, that identity depends; and as the very essence
of these relations consists in their producing an easy transition of
ideas; it follows, that our notions of personal identity, proceed entirely
from the smooth and uninterrupted progress of the thought along a train of
connected ideas, according to the principles above-explained.</p>
<p>The only question, therefore, which remains, is, by what relations this
uninterrupted progress of our thought is produced, when we consider the
successive existence of a mind or thinking person. And here it is evident
we must confine ourselves to resemblance and causation, and must drop
contiguity, which has little or no influence in the present case.</p>
<p>To begin with resemblance; suppose we coued see clearly into the breast of
another, and observe that succession of perceptions, which constitutes his
mind or thinking principle, and suppose that he always preserves the
memory of a considerable part of past perceptions; it is evident that
nothing coued more contribute to the bestowing a relation on this
succession amidst all its variations. For what is the memory but a
faculty, by which we raise up the images of past perceptions? And as an
image necessarily resembles its object, must not. The frequent placing of
these resembling perceptions in the chain of thought, convey the
imagination more easily from one link to another, and make the whole seem
like the continuance of one object? In this particular, then, the memory
not only discovers the identity, but also contributes to its production,
by producing the relation of resemblance among the perceptions. The case
is the same whether we consider ourselves or others.</p>
<p>As to causation; we may observe, that the true idea of the human mind, is
to consider it as a system of different perceptions or different
existences, which are linked together by the relation of cause and effect,
and mutually produce, destroy, influence, and modify each other. Our
impressions give rise to their correspondent ideas; said these ideas in
their turn produce other impressions. One thought chaces another, and
draws after it a third, by which it is expelled in its turn. In this
respect, I cannot compare the soul more properly to any thing than to a
republic or commonwealth, in which the several members are united by the
reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to other
persons, who propagate the same republic in the incessant changes of its
parts. And as the same individual republic may not only change its
members, but also its laws and constitutions; in like manner the same
person may vary his character and disposition, as well as his impressions
and ideas, without losing his identity. Whatever changes he endures, his
several parts are still connected by the relation of causation. And in
this view our identity with regard to the passions serves to corroborate
that with regard to the imagination, by the making our distant perceptions
influence each other, and by giving us a present concern for our past or
future pains or pleasures.</p>
<p>As a memory alone acquaints us with the continuance and extent of this
succession of perceptions, it is to be considered, upon that account
chiefly, as the source of personal identity. Had we no memory, we never
should have any notion of causation, nor consequently of that chain of
causes and effects, which constitute our self or person. But having once
acquired this notion of causation from the memory, we can extend the same
chain of causes, and consequently the identity of car persons beyond our
memory, and can comprehend times, and circumstances, and actions, which we
have entirely forgot, but suppose in general to have existed. For how few
of our past actions are there, of which we have any memory? Who can tell
me, for instance, what were his thoughts and actions on the 1st of January
1715, the 11th of March 1719, and the 3rd of August 1733? Or will he
affirm, because he has entirely forgot the incidents of these days, that
the present self is not the same person with the self of that time; and by
that means overturn all the most established notions of personal identity?
In this view, therefore, memory does not so much produce as discover
personal identity, by shewing us the relation of cause and effect among
our different perceptions. It will be incumbent on those, who affirm that
memory produces entirely our personal identity, to give a reason why we cm
thus extend our identity beyond our memory.</p>
<p>The whole of this doctrine leads us to a conclusion, which is of great
importance in the present affair, viz. that all the nice and subtile
questions concerning personal identity can never possibly be decided, and
are to be regarded rather as gramatical than as philosophical
difficulties. Identity depends on the relations of ideas; and these
relations produce identity, by means of that easy transition they
occasion. But as the relations, and the easiness of the transition may
diminish by insensible degrees, we have no just standard, by which we can
decide any dispute concerning the time, when they acquire or lose a title
to the name of identity. All the disputes concerning the identity of
connected objects are merely verbal, except so fax as the relation of
parts gives rise to some fiction or imaginary principle of union, as we
have already observed.</p>
<p>What I have said concerning the first origin and uncertainty of our notion
of identity, as applied to the human mind, may be extended with little or
no variation to that of simplicity. An object, whose different co-existent
parts are bound together by a close relation, operates upon the
imagination after much the same manner as one perfectly simple and
indivisible and requires not a much greater stretch of thought in order to
its conception. From this similarity of operation we attribute a
simplicity to it, and feign a principle of union as the support of this
simplicity, and the center of all the different parts and qualities of the
object.</p>
<p>Thus we have finished our examination of the several systems of
philosophy, both of the intellectual and natural world; and in our
miscellaneous way of reasoning have been led into several topics; which
will either illustrate and confirm some preceding part of this discourse,
or prepare the way for our following opinions. It is now time to return to
a more close examination of our subject, and to proceed in the accurate
anatomy of human nature, having fully explained the nature of our judgment
and understandings.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />