<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0035" id="link2H_4_0035"></SPAN></p>
<h2> SECT. XV. RULES BY WHICH TO JUDGE OF CAUSES AND EFFECTS. </h2>
<p>According to the precedent doctrine, there are no objects which by the
mere survey, without consulting experience, we can determine to be the
causes of any other; and no objects, which we can certainly determine in
the same manner not to be the causes. Any thing may produce any thing.
Creation, annihilation, motion, reason, volition; all these may arise from
one another, or from any other object we can imagine. Nor will this appear
strange, if we compare two principles explained above, THAT THE CONSTANT
CONJUNCTION OF OBJECTS DETERMINES THEIR CAUSATION, AND [Part I. Sect. 5.]
THAT, PROPERTY SPEAKING, NO OBJECTS ARE CONTRARY TO EACH OTHER BUT
EXISTENCE AND NON-EXISTENCE. Where objects are not contrary, nothing
hinders them from having that constant conjunction, on which the relation
of cause and effect totally depends.</p>
<p>Since therefore it is possible for all objects to become causes or effects
to each other, it may be proper to fix some general rules, by which we may
know when they really are so.</p>
<p>(1) The cause and effect must be contiguous in space and time.</p>
<p>(2) The cause must be prior to the effect.</p>
<p>(3) There must be a constant union betwixt the cause and effect. It is
chiefly this quality, that constitutes the relation.</p>
<p>(4) The same cause always produces the same effect, and the same effect
never arises but from the same cause. This principle we derive from
experience, and is the source of most of our philosophical reasonings. For
when by any clear experiment we have discovered the causes or effects of
any phaenomenon, we immediately extend our observation to every phenomenon
of the same kind, without waiting for that constant repetition, from which
the first idea of this relation is derived.</p>
<p>(5) There is another principle, which hangs upon this, viz. that where
several different objects produce the same effect, it must be by means of
some quality, which we discover to be common amongst them. For as like
effects imply like causes, we must always ascribe the causation to the
circumstance, wherein we discover the resemblance.</p>
<p>(6) The following principle is founded on the same reason. The difference
in the effects of two resembling objects must proceed from that
particular, in which they differ. For as like causes always produce like
effects, when in any instance we find our expectation to be disappointed,
we must conclude that this irregularity proceeds from some difference in
the causes.</p>
<p>(7) When any object encreases or diminishes with the encrease or
diminution of its cause, it is to be regarded as a compounded effect,
derived from the union of the several different effects, which arise from
the several different parts of the cause. The absence or presence of one
part of the cause is here supposed to be always attended with the absence
or presence of a proportionable part of the effect. This constant
conjunction sufficiently proves, that the one part is the cause of the
other. We must, however, beware not to draw such a conclusion from a few
experiments. A certain degree of heat gives pleasure; if you diminish that
heat, the pleasure diminishes; but it does not follow, that if you augment
it beyond a certain degree, the pleasure will likewise augment; for we
find that it degenerates into pain.</p>
<p>(8) The eighth and last rule I shall take notice of is, that an object,
which exists for any time in its full perfection without any effect, is
not the sole cause of that effect, but requires to be assisted by some
other principle, which may forward its influence and operation. For as
like effects necessarily follow from like causes, and in a contiguous time
and place, their separation for a moment shews, that these causes are not
compleat ones.</p>
<p>Here is all the LOGIC I think proper to employ in my reasoning; and
perhaps even this was not very necessary, but might have been supplyd by
the natural principles of our understanding. Our scholastic head-pieces
and logicians shew no such superiority above the mere vulgar in their
reason and ability, as to give us any inclination to imitate them in
delivering a long system of rules and precepts to direct our judgment, in
philosophy. All the rules of this nature are very easy in their invention,
but extremely difficult in their application; and even experimental
philosophy, which seems the most natural and simple of any, requires the
utmost stretch of human judgment. There is no phaenomenon in nature, but
what is compounded and modifyd by so many different circumstances, that in
order to arrive at the decisive point, we must carefully separate whatever
is superfluous, and enquire by new experiments, if every particular
circumstance of the first experiment was essential to it. These new
experiments are liable to a discussion of the same kind; so that the
utmost constancy is requird to make us persevere in our enquiry, and the
utmost sagacity to choose the right way among so many that present
themselves. If this be the case even in natural philosophy, how much more
in moral, where there is a much greater complication of circumstances, and
where those views and sentiments, which are essential to any action of the
mind, are so implicit and obscure, that they often escape our strictest
attention, and are not only unaccountable in their causes, but even
unknown in their existence? I am much afraid lest the small success I meet
with in my enquiries will make this observation bear the air of an apology
rather than of boasting.</p>
<p>If any thing can give me security in this particular, it will be the
enlarging of the sphere of my experiments as much as possible; for which
reason it may be proper in this place to examine the reasoning faculty of
brutes, as well as that of human creatures.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />