<p><SPAN name="link2H_4_0015" id="link2H_4_0015"></SPAN></p>
<h2> SECT. II. OF THE INFINITE DIVISIBILITY OF SPACE AND TIME. </h2>
<p>Wherever ideas are adequate representations of objects, the relations,
contradictions and agreements of the ideas are all applicable to the
objects; and this we may in general observe to be the foundation of all
human knowledge. But our ideas are adequate representations of the most
minute parts of extension; and through whatever divisions and subdivisions
we may suppose these parts to be arrived at, they can never become
inferior to some ideas, which we form. The plain consequence is, that
whatever appears impossible and contradictory upon the comparison of these
ideas, must be really impossible and contradictory, without any farther
excuse or evasion.</p>
<p>Every thing capable of being infinitely divided contains an infinite
number of parts; otherwise the division would be stopt short by the
indivisible parts, which we should immediately arrive at. If therefore any
finite extension be infinitely divisible, it can be no contradiction to
suppose, that a finite extension contains an infinite number of parts: And
vice versa, if it be a contradiction to suppose, that a finite extension
contains an infinite number of parts, no finite extension can be
infinitely divisible. But that this latter supposition is absurd, I easily
convince myself by the consideration of my clear ideas. I first take the
least idea I can form of a part of extension, and being certain that there
is nothing more minute than this idea, I conclude, that whatever I
discover by its means must be a real quality of extension. I then repeat
this idea once, twice, thrice, &c., and find the compound idea of
extension, arising from its repetition, always to augment, and become
double, triple, quadruple, &c., till at last it swells up to a
considerable bulk, greater or smaller, in proportion as I repeat more or
less the same idea. When I stop in the addition of parts, the idea of
extension ceases to augment; and were I to carry on the addition in
infinitum, I clearly perceive, that the idea of extension must also become
infinite. Upon the whole, I conclude, that the idea of all infinite number
of parts is individually the same idea with that of an infinite extension;
that no finite extension is capable of containing an infinite number of
parts; and consequently that no finite extension is infinitely divisible
[FN 3.].</p>
<p>[FN 3. It has been objected to me, that infinite<br/>
divisibility supposes only an infinite number of<br/>
PROPORTIONAL not of ALIQIOT parts, and that an infinite<br/>
number of proportional parts does not form an infinite<br/>
extension. But this distinction is entirely frivolous.<br/>
Whether these parts be calld ALIQUOT or PROPORTIONAL, they<br/>
cannot be inferior to those minute parts we conceive; and<br/>
therefore cannot form a less extension by their<br/>
conjunction.]<br/></p>
<p>I may subjoin another argument proposed by a noted author [Mons.
MALEZIEU], which seems to me very strong and beautiful. It is evident,
that existence in itself belongs only to unity, and is never applicable to
number, but on account of the unites, of which the number is composed.
Twenty men may be said to exist; but it is only because one, two, three,
four, &c. are existent, and if you deny the existence of the latter,
that of the former falls of course. It is therefore utterly absurd to
suppose any number to exist, and yet deny the existence of unites; and as
extension is always a number, according to the common sentiment of
metaphysicians, and never resolves itself into any unite or indivisible
quantity, it follows, that extension can never at all exist. It is in vain
to reply, that any determinate quantity of extension is an unite; but
such-a-one as admits of an infinite number of fractions, and is
inexhaustible in its sub-divisions. For by the same rule these twenty men
may be considered as a unit. The whole globe of the earth, nay the whole
universe, may be considered as a unit. That term of unity is merely a
fictitious denomination, which the mind may apply to any quantity of
objects it collects together; nor can such an unity any more exist alone
than number can, as being in reality a true number. But the unity, which
can exist alone, and whose existence is necessary to that of all number,
is of another kind, and must be perfectly indivisible, and incapable of
being resolved into any lesser unity.</p>
<p>All this reasoning takes place with regard to time; along with an
additional argument, which it may be proper to take notice of. It is a
property inseparable from time, and which in a manner constitutes its
essence, that each of its parts succeeds another, and that none of them,
however contiguous, can ever be co-existent. For the same reason, that the
year 1737 cannot concur with the present year 1738 every moment must be
distinct from, and posterior or antecedent to another. It is certain then,
that time, as it exists, must be composed of indivisible moments. For if
in time we could never arrive at an end of division, and if each moment,
as it succeeds another, were not perfectly single and indivisible, there
would be an infinite number of co-existent moments, or parts of time;
which I believe will be allowed to be an arrant contradiction.</p>
<p>The infinite divisibility of space implies that of time, as is evident
from the nature of motion. If the latter, therefore, be impossible, the
former must be equally so.</p>
<p>I doubt not but, it will readily be allowed by the most obstinate defender
of the doctrine of infinite divisibility, that these arguments are
difficulties, and that it is impossible to give any answer to them which
will be perfectly clear and satisfactory. But here we may observe, that
nothing can be more absurd, than this custom of calling a difficulty what
pretends to be a demonstration, and endeavouring by that means to elude
its force and evidence. It is not in demonstrations as in probabilities,
that difficulties can take place, and one argument counter-ballance
another, and diminish its authority. A demonstration, if just, admits of
no opposite difficulty; and if not just, it is a mere sophism, and
consequently can never be a difficulty. It is either irresistible, or has
no manner of force. To talk therefore of objections and replies, and
ballancing of arguments in such a question as this, is to confess, either
that human reason is nothing but a play of words, or that the person
himself, who talks so, has not a Capacity equal to such subjects.
Demonstrations may be difficult to be comprehended, because of
abstractedness of the subject; but can never have such difficulties as
will weaken their authority, when once they are comprehended.</p>
<p>It is true, mathematicians are wont to say, that there are here equally
strong arguments on the other side of the question, and that the doctrine
of indivisible points is also liable to unanswerable objections. Before I
examine these arguments and objections in detail, I will here take them in
a body, and endeavour by a short and decisive reason to prove at once,
that it is utterly impossible they can have any just foundation.</p>
<p>It is an established maxim in metaphysics, That whatever the mind clearly
conceives, includes the idea of possible existence, or in other words,
that nothing we imagine is absolutely impossible. We can form the idea of
a golden mountain, and from thence conclude that such a mountain may
actually exist. We can form no idea of a mountain without a valley, and
therefore regard it as impossible.</p>
<p>Now it is certain we have an idea of extension; for otherwise why do we
talk and reason concerning it? It is likewise certain that this idea, as
conceived by the imagination, though divisible into parts or inferior
ideas, is not infinitely divisible, nor consists of an infinite number of
parts: For that exceeds the comprehension of our limited capacities. Here
then is an idea of extension, which consists of parts or inferior ideas,
that are perfectly, indivisible: consequently this idea implies no
contradiction: consequently it is possible for extension really to exist
conformable to it: and consequently all the arguments employed against the
possibility of mathematical points are mere scholastick quibbles, and
unworthy of our attention.</p>
<p>These consequences we may carry one step farther, and conclude that all
the pretended demonstrations for the infinite divisibility of extension
are equally sophistical; since it is certain these demonstrations cannot
be just without proving the impossibility of mathematical points; which it
is an evident absurdity to pretend to.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />