<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<h1>LITTLE MASTERPIECES OF SCIENCE</h1>
<div class="figcenter"> <ANTIMG src="images/il004.png" width-obs="305" height-obs="500" alt="John Fiske" title="John Fiske" /> <span class="caption">John Fiske</span></div>
<hr class="br" /></div>
<div class="bbox">
<p class="center p150 mt1"><span class="big">Little Masterpieces<br/>
of Science</span></p>
<p class="center p150 mt1">Edited by George Iles</p>
</div>
<div class="bbox">
<h2><span class="big">MIND</span></h2>
<p class="center p140"><i>By</i></p>
<div class='center'>
<table border="0" cellpadding="4" cellspacing="0" summary="">
<tr><td align='left'>John Fiske</td><td align='left'>Oliver W. Holmes</td></tr>
<tr><td align='left'>James Sully</td><td align='left'>Henry Maudsley</td></tr>
<tr><td align='left'>Francis Galton</td><td align='left'>William B. Carpenter</td></tr>
<tr><td align='left'>William H. Hudson</td><td align='left'>Thomas H. Huxley</td></tr>
</table></div>
<hr class="br" />
<div class="figcenter"> <ANTIMG src="images/il005.png" width-obs="125" height-obs="116" alt="Decoration" title="Decoration" /></div>
</div>
<div class="bbox">
<div class='center'><b>NEW YORK</b><br/>
<b>DOUBLEDAY, PAGE & COMPANY</b><br/>
1902</div>
</div>
<hr class="br" />
<div class="center">
Copyright, 1900, by Houghton, Mifflin & Co.<br/>
Copyright, 1902, by Doubleday, Page & Co.<br/>
Copyright, 1895, by D. Appleton & Co.<br/></div>
<div class="trans-note"><span class="smcap"><b>Transcriber's Note</b></span>:
<p>Hyphenated and accented words have been standardized. Obvious printers
errors, including punctuation have been silently corrected.
Undevelopment, unseizable, traru, although not valid words, make sense
in the context and I have therefore left them as in the original. All
other inconsistencies have been left as in the original except where
noted at the end of this file.</p>
</div>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak">PREFACE</h2></div>
<p>The study of mind was advanced as remarkably during the nineteenth
century as any of its sister sciences. Here, as elsewhere, observation
grew keener, new instrumental tests were adopted, and interpretation
became more sagacious. A fact as commonplace as the length of human
babyhood, when it came under the eye of John Fiske, went far to explain
the foundations of the family, and how it came about that primitive man,
to whom much was given, so added to his gifts that at last the gulf
betwixt him and his next of kin became all but infinite. Of the new
study of children, which owes a weighty debt to Darwin and Preyer,
Professor Sully is a worthy exponent. In this volume he has something to
say of the deepest interest to parents, to all students of the early
unfolding of human faculty. In the inquiry of Mr. Galton regarding Twins
we have a sterling example of the statistical method. Who shall call
that method dry and unfruitful after he reads what it brought to this
patient and discerning investigator?</p>
<p>If it be assumed that there is nothing in the mind that has not been in
the senses, it becomes a question of importance, How may sight, the
noblest of the senses, come to its best estate? Has it been affected for
good or harm by civilized life? This question is discussed with shrewd
humour by Mr. Hudson in his chapter on the sight of savages. One of the
most promising fields of research directs its quest to the riches
commonly hid beneath the surface of the mental sea. It seems probable
that before the close of the twentieth century means may be discovered
of sounding the depths of unconscious and sub-conscious being, means
comparable with the powers of exploration which the X-ray has bestowed
upon the physicist. To this alluring field of inquiry no better
introduction can be given than Dr. Holmes affords us in this volume. Dr.
Maudsley's chapter on Memory treats a faculty which lies at the base of
all mental wealth, the talent for accumulation, the ability to command
at will every item of the mind's crowded treasure-house. Whether
remembered or forgotten, every impression stamped upon a sound, capable
brain, goes to build up and refine the judgment. This power, under the
name of Common Sense, is treated by Dr. Carpenter with the fulness of
suggestion which always marked that veteran thinker.</p>
<p>The main value of the study of the mind is after all, to direct the
development of mind. No spokesman of science ever urged the reform of
education with so much force as Huxley. Two of his pleas are here
presented; they have lost little of their point with the flight of
years. His argument for laboratory practice has, happily, borne abundant
fruit on both sides of the Atlantic. Manual training, the elementary
form of that practice, is now taught in thousands of our public schools,
and should be freely offered in all. It means putting boys and girls in
full possession of themselves, with a profound impetus to intelligence
when a knowledge of things replaces the repetition of symbols.</p>
<p>The reader may wish to extend his survey of the science of mind beyond
the books laid under contribution in this volume. No better author can
be recommended than Professor William James, of Harvard University. His
“Talks to Teachers on Psychology” is as instructive and delightful to
the ordinary reader as to the audience for which it was specially
written. Professor James's “Principles of Psychology,” in two volumes,
and “Briefer Course in Psychology,” in one volume, are for systematic
study. All three works are published by Henry Holt & Co., New York.</p>
<p style="text-align: right;"><span class="smcap">George Iles.</span></p>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak">CONTENTS</h2></div>
<p><SPAN name="toc" id="toc"></SPAN></p>
<div class="center">
<table border="0" cellpadding="4" cellspacing="0" summary="Table of Contents" width="80%">
<colgroup>
<col width="90%" />
<col width="10%" />
</colgroup>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">FISKE, JOHN</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#THE_PART_PLAYED_BY_INFANCY_IN_THE_EVOLUTION_OF_MAN"><b><span class="smcap">The Part Played by Infancy in the Evolution of Man.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">Wallace pointed out that when once the intelligence of man
became dominant, his body would change but little. Wallace
brought up a baby orang-outang which had a period of infantile
helplessness much longer than that of a lamb or a calf. The
still longer infancy of the human babe was most significant
to John Fiske. It showed that the highest nervous development
is the slowest. The prolongation of infancy lengthens the
period of maternal affection, tends to keep parents and
children together, and thus the institution of the family is
founded. Progress has been in the direction of bringing out
the higher spiritual attributes of man: hence the elemental
truth of religion.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_3">3</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">SULLY, JAMES</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#THE_NEW_STUDY_OF_CHILDREN"><b><span class="smcap">The New Study of Children.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">Man has the child always with him. The study of the child
is now scientific. The unfoldings of an infant mind throw
light on the development of the human race. Child-study is
necessary if education is to be rightly directed. Children
often reticent: sometimes ask strange questions. To understand
children, love and knowledge are required. Observation,
experiment and their records. Individual cases should be
compared on a large scale.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_21">21</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">GALTON, FRANCIS</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#TWINS_THEIR_HISTORY_AS_A_CRITERION_OF_THE_RELATIVE_POWERS_OF_NATURE_AND"><b><span class="smcap">Twins, Their History as a Criterion of the<br/> Relative Powers of
Nature and Nurture.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">Twins alike by nature may as adults be compared to note how
far diversity of circumstance has been influential. Twins
unlike by nature and educated alike show how far nurture
compares with inherited qualities as determining character.
Extraordinary cases of resemblance: twins widely separated
develop the same disease or mania at the same time. Only
illness or accident causes difference between twins alike
in early life. Twins originally unlike so remain, although
educated alike. Nature vastly stronger than nurture in the
making of man.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_53">53</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">HUDSON, WILLIAM H.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#SIGHT_IN_SAVAGES"><b><span class="smcap">Sight in Savages.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">Keen observation of cards by a player whose vision otherwise
was ordinary. We see what we look for. Sight in savages is
trained to detect particular objects,—men, beasts and birds
of prey, reptiles, game and the like. Sight in civilized
man is just as sharp, but is directed to different objects,
the letters of a printed page, for example.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_79">79</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">HOLMES, OLIVER W.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#MECHANISM_IN_THOUGHT_AND_MORALS"><b><span class="smcap">Mechanism in Thought and Morals.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">Do we ever think without knowing that we are thinking? Leibnitz
long ago said yes. We remember a name by ceasing the conscious
search for it. One goes to sleep with a problem in mind, and
awakens with the solution clear. The man of genius is inspired
he knows not how: the deepest things are not in the consciousness.
How Burns composed his poems. An idea planted in a thinker's
mind will grow when he is least conscious of growth.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_95">95</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">MAUDSLEY, HENRY</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#MEMORY"><b><span class="smcap">Memory.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">Unless the mind retains impressions and can recall them, no
development is possible. Acts at first difficult become easy
because nerves and muscles remember. Attention is the mother
of memory. The more various and intimate the association
of ideas the better.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_115">115</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">CARPENTER, WILLIAM B.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#COMMON_SENSE"><b><span class="smcap">Common Sense.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">Walking and other common movements of the body become all
but automatic. In much the same way mental experiences
become organized into judgments which are largely or wholly
true. Judgment in mathematics or other sciences demands
special training. Grammar is often unconsciously acquired.
The intuitions of the practised detective. The desire to
do right strengthens the intellect. A wise man trusts to
the spontaneities of his mind, just as a rider may trust
his horse to find its way home. The human race, like the
individual man, grows in common sense, abandons absurd
practices and beliefs.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_131">131</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">HUXLEY, THOMAS H.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#A_LIBERAL_EDUCATION"><b><span class="smcap">A Liberal Education.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">If we are to win the game of life we must understand and obey
its rules. No man wholly uneducated. A liberal education
makes the most of body, mind and heart. Education to the
poor is of supreme importance: reading and writing are
merely the means of education. The classics should be taught
in a scientific way. Thorough knowledge of the earth as a
centre from which study may proceed. Literature and history
are indispensable.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_151">151</SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td class="tdh">HUXLEY, THOMAS H.</td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td align='center'><SPAN href="#SCIENCE_AND_CULTURE"><b><span class="smcap">Science and Culture.</span></b></SPAN></td>
</tr>
<tr>
<td><p class="hang">The themes of classical education are less important than
those of science. For culture an exclusively scientific
education is at least as effectual as an exclusively literary
education. New knowledge has so much increased in modern
times as to sway daily life. The scientific method is now
recognized as the one mode of discerning or discovering
truth. What in the past men said about things is vastly
less to the point than what can be learned now at first
hand. The Greeks looked to Nature, let us also look to
Nature and not merely repeat what the Greeks reported.
Modern languages, especially English, as means of culture.
Science cannot be applied unless its principles are understood.
The mastery of these principles is culture. Art and letters,
no less than science, are needed for a well-rounded mind.</p>
</td>
<td align='right'><SPAN href="#Page_171">171</SPAN></td>
</tr>
</table></div>
<hr />
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_1" id="Page_1">[Pg 1]</SPAN></span></p>
<div class="center" style="font-size: 200%">MIND</div>
</div>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="THE_PART_PLAYED_BY_INFANCY_IN_THE_EVOLUTION_OF_MAN" id="THE_PART_PLAYED_BY_INFANCY_IN_THE_EVOLUTION_OF_MAN"></SPAN>THE PART PLAYED BY INFANCY IN<br/> THE EVOLUTION OF MAN</h2>
<p><span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></p>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_3" id="Page_3">[Pg 3]</SPAN></span></p>
</div>
<h3><span class="smcap">John Fiske</span></h3>
<div class="noteb"><p>[John Fiske attained distinction in three distinct fields of
letters: as a historian, as a scientific interpreter of
religion, as an expositor of the philosophy of evolution. In
this last department of his work his original contribution
was the theory here set forth, taken from a chapter in “A
Century of Science and Other Essays,” copyright by Houghton,
Mifflin & Co., Boston and New York, 1900. Mr. Fiske died in
1901, in his sixtieth year.]</p>
</div>
<p>When Darwin's “Origin of Species” was first published, when it gave us
that wonderful explanation of the origin of forms of life from allied
forms through the operation of natural selection, it must have been like
a mental illumination to every person who comprehended it. But after all
it left a great many questions unexplained, as was natural. It accounted
for the phenomena of organic development in general with wonderful
success, but it must have left a great many minds with the feeling: If
man has been produced in this way, if the mere operation of natural
selection has produced the human race, wherein is the human race anyway
essentially different from lower races? Is not man really dethroned,
taken down from that exceptional position in which we have been
accustomed to place him, and<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_4" id="Page_4">[Pg 4]</SPAN></span> might it not be possible, in the course of
the future, for other beings to come upon the earth as far superior to
man as man is superior to the fossilized dragons of Jurassic antiquity?</p>
<p>Such questions used to be asked, and when they were asked, although one
might have a very strong feeling that it was not so, at the same time
one could not exactly say why. One could not then find any scientific
argument for objections to that point of view. But with the further
development of the question the whole subject began gradually to wear a
different appearance; and I am going to give you a little bit of
autobiography, because I think it may be of some interest in this
connection. I am going to mention two or three of the successive stages
which the whole question took in my own mind as one thing came up after
another, and how from time to time it began to dawn upon me that I had
up to that point been looking at the problem from not exactly the right
point of view.</p>
<p>When Darwin's “Descent of Man” was published in 1871, it was of course a
book characterized by all his immense learning, his wonderful fairness
of spirit and fertility of suggestion. Still, one could not but feel
that it did not solve the question of the origin of man. There was one
great contrast between that book and his “Origin of Species.” In the
earlier treatise he undertook to point out a <i>vera causa</i> [true cause]
of the origin of species, and he did it. In his “Descent of Man” he
brought together a great<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_5" id="Page_5">[Pg 5]</SPAN></span> many minor generalizations which facilitated
the understanding of man's origin. But he did not come at all near to
solving the central problem, nor did he anywhere show clearly why the
natural selection might not have gone on forever producing one set of
beings after another distinguishable chiefly by physical differences.
But Darwin's co-discoverer, Alfred Russel Wallace, at an early stage in
his researches, struck out a most brilliant and pregnant suggestion. In
that one respect Wallace went further than ever Darwin did. It was a
point of which, indeed, Darwin admitted the importance. It was a point
of which nobody could fail to understand the importance, that in the
course of the evolution of a very highly organized animal, if there came
a point at which it was of more advantage to that animal to have
variations in his intelligence seized upon and improved by natural
selection than to have physical changes seized upon, then natural
selection would begin working almost exclusively upon that creature's
intelligence, and he would develop in intelligence to a great extent,
while his physical organism would change but slightly. Now, that of
course applied to the case of man, who is changed physically but very
slightly from the apes, while he has traversed intellectually such a
stupendous chasm.</p>
<p>As soon as this statement was made by Wallace, it seemed to me to open
up an entirely new world of speculation. There was this<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_6" id="Page_6">[Pg 6]</SPAN></span> enormous
antiquity of man, during the greater part of which he did not know
enough to make history. We see man existing here on the earth, no one
can say how long, but surely many hundreds of thousands of years, yet
only during just the last little fringe of four or five thousand years
has he arrived at the point where he makes history. Before that,
something was going on, a great many things were going on, while his
ancestors were slowly growing up to that point of intelligence where it
began to make itself felt in the recording of events. This agrees with
Wallace's suggestion of a long period of psychical change, accompanied
by slight physical change.</p>
<p>Well, in the spring of 1871, when Darwin's “Descent of Man” came out,
just about the same time I happened to be reading Wallace's account of
his experiences in the Malay Archipelago, and how at one time he caught
a female orang-outang with a new-born baby, and the mother died, and
Wallace brought up the baby orang-outang by hand; and this baby
orang-outang had a kind of infancy which was a great deal longer than
that of a cow or a sheep, but it was nothing compared to human infancy
in length. This little orang-outang could not get up and march around,
as mammals of less intelligence do, when he was first born, or within
three or four days; but after three or four weeks or so he would get up,
and begin taking hold of something and pushing it around, just as
children push a chair; and he went through a period of<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_7" id="Page_7">[Pg 7]</SPAN></span> staring at his
hands, as human babies do, and altogether was a good deal slower in
getting to the point where he could take care of himself. And while I
was reading of that I thought, Dear me! if there is any one thing in
which the human race is signally distinguished from other mammals, it is
in the enormous duration of their infancy; but it is a point that I do
not recollect ever seeing any naturalist so much as allude to.</p>
<p>It happened at just that time that I was making researches in psychology
about the organization of experiences, the way in which conscious
intelligent action can pass down into quasi-automatic action, the
generation of instincts, and various allied questions; and I thought,
Can it be that the increase of intelligence in an animal, if carried
beyond a certain point, must necessarily result in prolongation of the
period of infancy,—must necessarily result in the birth of the mammal
at a less developed stage, leaving something to be done, leaving a good
deal to be done, after birth? And then the argument seemed to come along
very naturally, that for every action of life, every adjustment which a
creature makes in life, whether a muscular adjustment or an intelligent
adjustment, there has got to be some registration effected in the
nervous system, some line of transit worn for nervous force to follow;
there has got to be a connection between certain nerve-centres before
the thing can be done, whether it is the acts of the viscera or the acts
of the limbs, or anything<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_8" id="Page_8">[Pg 8]</SPAN></span> of that sort; and of course it is obvious
that if the creature has not many things to register in his nervous
system, if he has a life which is very simple, consisting of few actions
that are performed with great frequency, that animal becomes almost
automatic in his whole life; and all the nervous connections that need
to be made to enable him to carry on life get made during the fœtal
period [the period before birth] or during the egg period, and when he
comes to be born, he comes all ready to go to work. As one result of
this, he does not learn from individual experience, but one generation
is like the preceding generations, with here and there some slight
modifications. But when you get the creature that has arrived at the
point where his experience has become varied, he has got to do a good
many things, and there is more or less individuality about them; and
many of them are not performed with the same minuteness and regularity,
so that there does not begin to be that automatism within the period
during which he is being developed and his form is taking on its
outlines. During prenatal life [before birth] there is not time enough
for all these nervous registrations, and so by degrees it comes about
that he is born with his nervous system perfectly capable only of making
him breathe and digest food,—of making him do the things absolutely
requisite for supporting life; instead of being born with a certain
number of definite developed capacities, he has a<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_9" id="Page_9">[Pg 9]</SPAN></span> number of
potentialities which have got to be roused according to his own
individual experience. Pursuing that line of thought, it began after a
while to seem clear to me that the infancy of the animal in a very
undeveloped condition, with the larger part of his faculties in
potentiality rather than in actuality, was a direct result of the
increase of intelligence, and I began to see that now we have two steps:
first, natural selection goes on increasing the intelligence; and
secondly, when the intelligence goes far enough, it makes a longer
infancy, a creature is born less developed, and therefore there comes
this plastic period during which he is more teachable. The capacity for
progress begins to come in, and you begin to get at one of the great
points in which man is distinguished from the lower animals, for one of
those points is undoubtedly his progressiveness; and I think that any
one will say, with very little hesitation, that if it were not for our
period of infancy we should not be progressive. If we came into the
world with our capacities all cut and dried, one generation would be
very much like another.</p>
<p>Then, looking around to see what are the other points which are most
important in which man differs from the lower animals, there comes that
matter of the family. The family has adumbrations and foreshadowings
among the lower animals, but in general it may be said that while
mammals lower than man are gregarious, in man have become established
those<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_10" id="Page_10">[Pg 10]</SPAN></span> peculiar relationships which constitute what we know as the
family; and it is easy to see how the existence of helpless infants
would bring about just that state of things. The necessity of caring for
the infants would prolong the period of maternal affection, and would
tend to keep the father and mother and children together, but it would
tend especially to keep the mother and children together. This business
of the marital relations was not really a thing that became adjusted in
the primitive ages of man, but it has become adjusted in the course of
civilization. Real monogamy, real faithfulness of the male parent,
belongs to a comparatively advanced stage; but in the earlier stages the
knitting together of permanent relations between mother and infant, and
the approximation toward steady relations on the part of the male
parent, came to bring about the family and gradually to knit those
organizations which we know as clans.</p>
<p>Here we come to another stage, another step forward. The instant society
becomes organized in clans, natural selection cannot let these clans be
broken up and die out,—the clan becomes the chief object or care of
natural selection, because, if you destroy it you retrograde again, you
lose all you have gained; consequently, those clans in which the
primeval selfish instincts were so modified that the individual conduct
would be subordinated to some extent to the needs to the clan,—those
are the ones which would prevail<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_11" id="Page_11">[Pg 11]</SPAN></span> in the struggle for life. In this way
you gradually get an external standard to which man has to conform his
conduct, and you get the germs of altruism and morality; and in the
prolonged affectionate relation between the mother and the infant you
get the opportunity for that development of altruistic feeling which,
once started in those relations, comes into play in the more general
relations, and makes more feasible and more workable the bonds which
keep society together, and enable it to unite on wider and wider terms.</p>
<p>So it seems that from a very small beginning we are reaching a very
considerable result. I had got these facts pretty clearly worked out,
and carried them around with me some years, before a fresh conclusion
came over me one day with a feeling of surprise. In the old days before
the Copernican astronomy was promulgated, man regarded himself as the
centre of the universe. He used to entertain theological systems which
conformed to his limited knowledge of nature. The universe seemed to be
made for his uses, the earth seemed to have been fitted up for his
dwelling-place, he occupied the centre of creation, the sun was made to
give him light, etc. When Copernicus overthrew that view, the effect
upon theology was certainly tremendous. I do not believe that justice
has ever been done to the shock that it gave to man when he was made to
realize that he occupied a kind of miserable little clod of dirt in the<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_12" id="Page_12">[Pg 12]</SPAN></span>
universe, and that there were so many other worlds greater than this. It
was one of the first great shocks involved in the change from ancient to
modern scientific views, and I do not doubt it was responsible for a
great deal of the pessimistic philosophizing that came in the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries.</p>
<p>Now, it flashed upon me a dozen years or so ago—after thinking about
this manner in which man originated—that man occupies certainly just as
exceptional a position as before, if he is the terminal in a long series
of evolutionary events. If at the end of the long history of evolution
comes man, if this whole secular process has been going on to produce
this supreme object, it does not much matter what kind of a cosmical
body he lives on. He is put back into the old position of theological
importance, and in a much more intelligent way than in the old days when
he was supposed to occupy the centre of the universe. We are enabled to
say that while there is no doubt of the evolutionary process going on
through countless ages which we know nothing about, yet in the one case
where it is brought home to us we spell out an intelligible story, and
we do find things working along up to man as a terminal fact in the
whole process. This is indeed a consistent conclusion from Wallace's
suggestion that natural selection, in working toward the genesis of man,
began to follow a new path and make psychical changes instead of
physical changes. Obviously, here<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_13" id="Page_13">[Pg 13]</SPAN></span> you are started upon a new chapter in
the history of the universe. It is no longer going to be necessary to
shape new limbs, and to thicken the skin and make new growths of hair,
when man has learned how to build a fire, when he can take some other
animal's hide and make it into clothes. You have got to a new state of
things.</p>
<p>After I had put together all these additional circumstances with regard
to the origination of human society and the development of altruism, I
began to see a little further into the matter. It then began to appear
that not only is man the terminal factor in a long process of evolution,
but in the origination of man there began the development of the higher
psychical attributes, and those attributes are coming to play a greater
and greater part in the development of the human race. Just take this
mere matter of “altruism,” as we call it. It is not a pretty word, but
must serve for want of a better. In the development of altruism from the
low point, where there was scarcely enough to hold the clan together, up
to the point reached at the present day, there has been a notable
progress, but there is still room for an enormous amount of improvement.
The progress has been all in the direction of bringing out what we call
the higher spiritual attributes. The feeling was now more strongly
impressed upon me than ever, that all these things tended to set the
whole doctrine of evolution into harmony with religion; that if the past
through which man had originated<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_14" id="Page_14">[Pg 14]</SPAN></span> was such as has been described, then
religion was a fit and worthy occupation for man, and some of the
assumptions which underlie every system of religion must be true. For
example, with regard to the assumption that what we see of the present
life is not the whole thing; that there is a spiritual side of the
question beside the material side; that, in short, there is for man a
life eternal. When I wrote the “Destiny of Man,” all that I ventured to
say was, that it did not seem quite compatible with ordinary common
sense to suppose that so much pains would have been taken to produce a
merely ephemeral result. But since then another argument has occurred to
me: that just at the time when the human race was beginning to come upon
the scene, when the germs of morality were coming in with the family,
when society was taking its first start, there came into the human
mind—how one can hardly say, but there did come—the beginnings of a
groping after something that lies outside and beyond the world of sense.
That groping after a spiritual world has been going on here for much
more than a hundred thousand years, and it has played an enormous part
in the history of mankind, in the whole development of human society.
Nobody can imagine what mankind would have been without it up to the
present time. Either all religion has been a reaching out for a phantom
that does not exist, or a reaching out after something that does exist,
but of which man, with his limited<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_15" id="Page_15">[Pg 15]</SPAN></span> intelligence, has only been able to
gain a crude idea. And the latter seems a far more probable conclusion,
because, if it is not so, it constitutes a unique exception to all the
operations of evolution we know about. As a general thing in the whole
history of evolution, when you see any internal adjustment reaching out
toward something, it is in order to adapt itself to something that
really exists; and if the religious cravings of man constitute an
exception, they are the one thing in the whole process of evolution that
is exceptional and different from all the rest. And this is surely an
argument of stupendous and resistless weight.</p>
<p>I take this autobiographical way of referring to these things, in the
order in which they came before my mind, for the sake of illustration.
The net result of the whole is to put evolution in harmony with
religious thought,—not necessarily in harmony with particular religious
dogmas or theories, but in harmony with the great religious drift, so
that the antagonism which used to appear to exist between religion and
science is likely to disappear. So I think it will before a great while.
If you take the case of some evolutionist like Professor Haeckel, who is
perfectly sure that materialism accounts for everything (he has got it
all cut and dried and settled; he knows all about it, so that there is
really no need of discussing the subject!); if you ask the question
whether it was his scientific study of evolution that really led him to
such a<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_16" id="Page_16">[Pg 16]</SPAN></span> dogmatic conclusion, or whether it was that he started from some
purely arbitrary assumption, like the French materialists of the
eighteenth century, I have no doubt that the latter would be the true
explanation. There are a good many people who start on their theories of
evolution with these ultimate questions all settled to begin with. It
was the most natural thing in the world that after the first assaults of
science upon old beliefs, after a certain number of Bible stories and a
certain number of church doctrines had been discredited, there should be
a school of men who in sheer weariness should settle down to scientific
researches, and say, “We content ourselves with what we can prove by the
methods of physical science, and we will throw everything else
overboard.” That was very much the state of mind of the famous French
atheists of the last century. But only think how chaotic nature was to
their minds compared to what she is to our minds to-day. Just think how
we have in the present century arrived where we can see the bearings of
one set of facts in nature as collated with another set of facts, and
contrast it with the view which even the greatest of those scientific
French materialists could take. Consider how fragmentary and how lacking
in arrangement was the universe they saw compared with the universe we
see to-day, and it is not strange that to them it could be an atheistic
world. That hostility between science and religion continued as long as
religion was linked<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_17" id="Page_17">[Pg 17]</SPAN></span> hand in hand with the ancient doctrine of special
creation. But now that the religious world has unmoored itself, now that
it is beginning to see the truth and beauty of natural science and to
look with friendship upon conceptions of evolution, I suspect that this
temporary antagonism, which we have fallen into a careless way of
regarding as an everlasting antagonism, will come to an end perhaps
quicker than we realize.</p>
<p>There is one point that is of great interest in this connection,
although I can only hint at it. Among the things that happened in that
dim past when man was coming into existence was the increase of his
powers of manipulation; and that was a factor of immense importance.
Anaxagoras, it is said, wrote a treatise in which he maintained that the
human race would never have become human if it had not been for the
hand. I do not know that there was so very much exaggeration about that.
It was certainly of great significance that the particular race of
mammals whose intelligence increased far enough to make it worth while
for natural selection to work upon intelligence alone was the race which
had developed hands and could manipulate things. It was a wonderful era
in the history of creation when that creature could take a club and use
it for a hammer, or could pry up a stone with a stake, thus adding one
more lever to the levers that made up his arm. From that day to this,
the career of man has been that of a person who has operated upon his
environment<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_18" id="Page_18">[Pg 18]</SPAN></span> in a different way from any animal before him. An era of
similar importance came probably somewhat later, when man learned how to
build a fire and cook his food. Here was another means of acting upon
the environment. Here was the beginning of the working of endless
physical and chemical changes through the application of heat, just as
the first use of the club or the crowbar was the beginning of an
enormous development in the mechanical arts.</p>
<p>Now, at the same time, to go back once more into that dim past, when
ethics and religion, manual art and scientific thought, found expression
in the crudest form of myths, the æsthetic sense was germinating
likewise. Away back in the glacial period you find pictures drawn and
scratched upon the reindeer's antler, portraitures of mammoths and
primitive pictures of the chase; you see the trinkets, the personal
decorations, proving beyond question that the æsthetic sense was there.
There has been an immense æsthetic development since then. And I believe
that in the future it is going to mean far more to us than we have yet
begun to realize. I refer to the kind of training that comes to mankind
through direct operation upon his environment, the incarnation of his
thought, the putting of his ideas into new material relations. This is
going to exert powerful effects of a civilizing kind. There is something
strongly educational and disciplinary in the mere dealing with matter,
whether it be in the manual training-school,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_19" id="Page_19">[Pg 19]</SPAN></span> whether it be in
carpentry, in overcoming the inherent and total depravity of inanimate
things, shaping them to your will, and also in learning to subject
yourself to their will (for sometimes you must do that in order to
achieve your conquests; in other words, you must humour their habits and
proclivities). In all this there is a priceless discipline, moral as
well as mental, let alone the fact that, in whatever kind of artistic
work a man does, he is doing that which in the very working has in it an
element of something outside of egoism; even if he is doing it for
motives not very altruistic, he is working toward a result the end of
which is the gratification or the benefit of other persons than himself;
he is working toward some result which in a measure depends upon their
approval, and to that extent tends to bring him into closer relations to
his fellow man.</p>
<p>In the future, to an even greater extent than in the recent past, crude
labour will be replaced by mechanical contrivances. The kind of labour
which can command its price is the kind which has trained intelligence
behind it. One of the great needs of our time is the multiplication of
skilled and special labour. The demand for the products of intelligence
is far greater than that for mere crude products of labour, and it will
be more and more so. For there comes a time when the latter products
have satisfied the limit to which a man can consume food and drink and
shelter,—those things which merely keep<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_20" id="Page_20">[Pg 20]</SPAN></span> the animal alive. But to those
things which minister to the requirements of the spiritual side of a man
there is almost no limit. The demand one can conceive is well-nigh
infinite. One of the philosophical things that have been said, in
discriminating man from the lower animals, is that he is the one
creature who is never satisfied. It is well for him that he is so, that
there is always something more for which he craves. To my mind this fact
most strongly hints that man is infinitely more than a mere animate
machine.</p>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="THE_NEW_STUDY_OF_CHILDREN" id="THE_NEW_STUDY_OF_CHILDREN"></SPAN>THE NEW STUDY OF CHILDREN</h2>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_21" id="Page_21">[Pg 21]</SPAN></span></p>
</div>
<p><span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></p>
<h3><span class="smcap">Professor James Sully</span></h3>
<div class="noteb"><p>[This eminent writer is Grote Professor of the Philosophy of
Mind and of Logic at University College, London. His works
published by D. Appleton & Co., New York, are “Illusions,”
“Outlines of Psychology with Special Reference to the Theory
of Education,” “Teachers' Handbook of Psychology,” “The Human
Mind,” “Pessimism,” “Children's Ways,” and “Studies of
Childhood.” From the last mentioned work, copyright by D.
Appleton & Co., the following is the introductory chapter.]</p>
</div>
<p>Man has always had the child with him, and one might be sure that since
he became gentle and alive to the beauty of things he must have come
under the spell of the baby. We have evidence beyond the oft-quoted
departure of Hector and other pictures of childish grace in early
literature that baby-worship and baby-subjection are not wholly things
of modern times. There is a pretty story taken down by Mr. Leland from
the lips of an old Indian woman, which relates how Glooskap, the
hero-god, after conquering all his enemies, rashly tried his hand at
managing a certain baby, Wasis by name, and how he got punished for his
rashness.</p>
<p>Yet there is good reason to suppose that it is only within comparatively
recent times that the more subtle charm and the deeper significance<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_22" id="Page_22">[Pg 22]</SPAN></span> of
infancy have been discerned. We have come to appreciate babyhood as we
have come to appreciate the finer lineaments of nature as a whole. This
applies of course more especially to the ruder sex. The man has in him
much of the boy's contempt for small things, and he needed ages of
education at the hands of the better-informed woman before he could
perceive the charm of infantile ways.</p>
<p>One of the first males to do justice to this attractive subject was
Rousseau. He made short work with the theological dogma that the child
is born morally depraved, and can only be made good by miraculous
appliances. His watchword, return to nature, included a reversion to the
infant as coming virginal and unspoilt by man's tinkering from the hands
of its Maker. To gain a glimpse of this primordial beauty before it was
marred by man's awkward touch was something, and so Rousseau set men in
the way of sitting reverently at the feet of infancy, watching and
learning.</p>
<p>For us of to-day, who have learned to go to the pure springs of nature
for much of our spiritual refreshment, the child has acquired a high
place among the things of beauty. Indeed, the grace of childhood may
almost be said to have been discovered by the modern poet. Wordsworth
has stooped over his cradle intent on catching, ere they passed, the
“visionary gleams” of “the glories he hath known.” Blake, R. L.
Stevenson, and others, have tried to put<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_23" id="Page_23">[Pg 23]</SPAN></span> into language his
day-dreamings, his quaint fancyings. Dickens and Victor Hugo have shown
us something of his delicate quivering heart-strings; Swinburne has
summed up the divine charm of “children's ways and wiles.” The page of
modern literature is, indeed, a monument of our child-love and our
child-admiration.</p>
<p>Nor is it merely as to a pure untarnished nature that we go back
admiringly to childhood. The æsthetic charm of the infant which draws us
so potently to its side and compels us to watch its words and actions
is, like everything else which moves the modern mind, highly complex.
Among other sources of this charm we may discern the perfect serenity,
the happy “insouciance” [unconcern] of the childish mind. The note of
world-complaint in modern life has penetrated into most domains, yet it
has not, one would hope, penetrated into the charmed circle of childish
experience. Childhood has, no doubt, its sad aspect:</p>
<div class="poem"><div class="stanza">
<span class="i0">Poor stumbler on the rocky coast of woe,<br/></span>
<span class="i0">Tutored by pain each source of pain to know:<br/></span></div>
</div>
<p>neglect and cruelty may bring much misery into the first bright years.
Yet the very instinct of childhood to be glad in its self-created world,
an instinct which with consummate art Victor Hugo keeps warm and quick
in the breast of the half-starved ill-used child Cosette, secures for it
a peculiar blessedness. The true nature-child,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_24" id="Page_24">[Pg 24]</SPAN></span> who has not become
used-up, is happy, untroubled with the future, knowing nothing of the
misery of disillusion. As, with hearts chastened by many experiences, we
take a peep over the wall of his fancy-built pleasance, we seem to be
taken back to a real golden age. With Amiel, we say: “The little of
paradise which still remains on earth is due to his presence.” Yet the
thought, which the same moment brings, of the flitting of the nursery
visions, of the coming storm and stress, adds a pathos to the spectacle,
and we feel as Heine felt when he wrote:</p>
<div class="poem"><div class="stanza">
<span class="i0">I look at you and sadness<br/></span>
<span class="i0">Steals into my heart.<br/></span></div>
</div>
<p>Other and strangely unlike feelings mingle with this caressing,
half-pitiful admiration. We moderns are given to relieving the strained
attitude of reverence and pity by momentary outbursts of humorous
merriment. The child, while appealing to our admiration and our pity,
makes a large and many-voiced appeal also to our sense of the laughter
in things. It is indeed hard to say whether he is most amusing when
setting at naught in his quiet, lordly way, our most extolled views, our
ideas of what is true and false, of the proper uses of things, and so
forth, or when labouring in his perfectly self-conceived fashion to
overtake us and be as experienced and as conventional as ourselves. This
ever new play of droll feature in childish thought<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_25" id="Page_25">[Pg 25]</SPAN></span> and action forms one
of the deepest sources of delight for the modern lover of childhood.</p>
<p>With the growth of a poetic or sentimental interest in childhood there
has come a new and different kind of interest. Ours is a scientific age,
and science has cast its inquisitive eye on the infant. We want to know
what happens in these first all-decisive two or three years of human
life, by what steps exactly the wee amorphous thing takes shape and
bulk, both physically and mentally. And we can now speak of the
beginning of a careful and methodical investigation of child-nature, by
men trained in scientific observation. This line of inquiry, started by
physicians, as the German Sigismund, in connection with their special
professional aims, has been carried on by a number of fathers and others
having access to the infant, among whom it may be enough to name Darwin
and Preyer.</p>
<p>This eagerness to know what the child is like, an eagerness illustrated
further by the number of reminiscences of early years recently
published, is the outcome of a many-sided interest which it may be worth
while to analyze.</p>
<p>The most obvious source of interest in the doings of infancy lies in its
primitiveness. At the cradle we are watching the beginnings of things,
the first tentative thrustings forward into life. Our modern science is
before all things historical and genetic, going back to beginnings so as
to understand the later and more complex<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_26" id="Page_26">[Pg 26]</SPAN></span> phases of things as the
outcome of these beginnings. The same kind of curiosity which prompts
the geologist to get back to the first stages in the building up of the
planet, or the biologist to search out the pristine forms of life, is
beginning to urge the student of man to discover by a careful study of
infancy the way in which human life begins to take its characteristic
forms.</p>
<p>The appearance of Darwin's name among those who have deemed the child
worthy of study suggests that the subject is closely connected with
natural history. However man in his proud maturity may be related to
Nature, it is certain that in his humble inception he is immersed in
Nature and saturated with her. As we all know, the lowest races of
mankind stand in close proximity to the animal world. The same is true
of the infants of civilized races. Their life is outward and visible,
forming a part of nature's spectacle; reason and will, the noble
prerogatives of humanity, are scarce discernible; sense, appetite,
instinct, these animal functions seem to sum up the first year of human
life.</p>
<p>To the evolutionist, moreover, the infant exhibits a still closer
kinship to the natural world. In the successive stages of fœtal
development he sees the gradual unfolding of human lineaments out of a
widely typical animal form. And even after birth he can discern new
evidences of this genealogical relation of the “lord” of creation to his
inferiors. How significant,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_27" id="Page_27">[Pg 27]</SPAN></span> for example, is the fact recently
established by a medical man, Dr. Louis Robinson, that the new-born
infant is able just like the ape to suspend his whole weight by grasping
a small horizontal rod.</p>
<p>Yet even as nature-object for the biologist the child presents
distinctive attributes. Though sharing in animal instinct, he shares in
it only to a very small extent. The most striking characteristic of the
new-born offspring of man is its unpreparedness for life. Compare with
the young of other animals the infant so feeble and incapable. He can
neither use his limbs nor see the distance of objects as a new-born
chick or calf is able to do. His brain-centres are, we are told, in a
pitiable state of undevelopment—and are not even securely encased
within their bony covering. Indeed, he resembles for all the world a
public building which has to be opened by a given date, and is found
when the day arrives to be in a humiliating state of incompleteness.</p>
<p>This fact of the special helplessness of the human offspring at birth,
of its long period of dependence on parental or other aids—a period
which, probably, tends to grow longer as civilization advances—is rich
in biological and sociological significance. For one thing, it
presupposes a specially high development of the protective and fostering
instincts in the human parents, and particularly the mother—for if the
helpless wee thing were not met by these<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_28" id="Page_28">[Pg 28]</SPAN></span> instincts, what would become
of our race? It is probable, too, as Mr. Spencer and others have argued,
that the institution by nature of this condition of infantile weakness
has reacted on the social affections of the race, helping to develop our
pitifulness for all frail and helpless things.</p>
<p>Nor is this all. The existence of the infant, with its large and
imperative claims, has been a fact of capital importance in the
development of social customs. Ethnological researches show that
communities have been much exercised with the problem of infancy, have
paid it the homage due to its supreme sacredness, girding it about with
a whole group of protective and beneficial customs.</p>
<p>Enough has been said, perhaps, to show the far-reaching significance of
babyhood to the modern savant. It is hardly too much to say that it has
become one of the most eloquent of nature's phenomena, telling us at
once of our affinity to the animal world, and of the forces by which our
race has, little by little, lifted itself to so exalted a position above
this world; and so it has happened that not merely to the perennial
baby-worshipper, the mother, and not merely to the poet touched with the
mystery of far off things, but to the grave man of science the infant
has become a centre of lively interest.</p>
<p>Nevertheless, it is not to the mere naturalist that the babe reveals all
its significance. Physical organism as it seems to be more than
anything<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_29" id="Page_29">[Pg 29]</SPAN></span> else, hardly more than a vegetative thing indeed, it carries
with it the germ of a human consciousness, and this consciousness begins
to expand and to form itself into a truly human shape from the very
beginning. And here a new source of interest presents itself. It is the
human psychologist, the student of those impalpable, unseizable,
evanescent phenomena which we call “state of consciousness,” who has a
supreme interest, and a scientific property in these first years of a
human existence. What is of most account in these crude tentatives at
living after the human fashion is the play of mind, the first
spontaneous manifestations of recognition, of reasoning expectation, of
feelings of sympathy and antipathy, of definite persistent purpose.</p>
<p>Rude, inchoate, vague enough, no doubt, are these first groping
movements of a human mind: yet of supreme value to the psychologist just
because they are the first. If, reflects the psychologist, he can only
get at this baby's consciousness so as to understand what is passing
there, he will be in an infinitely better position to find his way
through the intricacies of the adult consciousness. It may be, as we
shall see by-and-by, that the baby's mind is not so perfectly simple, so
absolutely primitive as it at first looks. Yet it is the simplest type
of human consciousness to which we can have access. The investigator of
this consciousness can never take any known sample of the animal mind as
his starting point if for no other reason than this, that while<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_30" id="Page_30">[Pg 30]</SPAN></span>
possessing many of the elements of the human mind, it presents these in
so unlike, so peculiar a pattern.</p>
<p>In this genetic tracing back of the complexities of man's mental life to
their primitive elements in the child's consciousness, questions of
peculiar interest will arise. A problem which though having a venerable
antiquity is still full of meaning concerns the precise relation of the
higher forms of intelligence and of sentiment to the elementary facts of
the individual's life-experience. Are we to regard all our ideas, even
those of God, as woven by the mind out of its experiences, as Locke
thought, or have we certain “innate ideas” from the first? Locke thought
he could settle this point by observing children. To-day, when the
philosophic emphasis is laid not on the date of appearance of the
“innate” intuition, but on its originality and spontaneity, this method
of interrogating the child's mind may seem less promising. Yet if of
less philosophical importance than was once supposed, it is of great
psychological importance. There are certain questions, such as that of
how we come to see things at a distance from us, which can be approached
most advantageously by a study of infant movements. In like manner I
believe the growth of a moral sentiment, of that feeling of reverence
for duty to which Kant gave so eloquent an expression, can only be
understood by the most painstaking observation of the mental activities
of the first years.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_31" id="Page_31">[Pg 31]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>There is, however, another, and in a sense a larger, source of
psychological interest in studying the processes and development of the
infant mind. It was pointed out above that to the evolutional biologist
the child exhibits man in his kinship to the lower sentient world. This
same evolutional point of view enables the psychologist to connect the
unfolding of an infant's mind with something which has gone before, with
the mental history of the race. According to this way of looking at
infancy the successive phases of its mental life are a brief <i>resume</i> of
the more important features in the slow upward progress of the species.
The periods dominated successively by sense and appetite, by blind
wondering and superstitious fancy, and by a calmer observation and a
juster reasoning about things, these steps mark the pathway both of the
child-mind and of the race-mind.</p>
<p>This being so, the first years of a child, with their imperfect verbal
expression, their crude fanciful ideas, their seizures by rage and
terror, their absorption in the present moment, acquire a new and
antiquarian interest. They mirror for us, in a diminished distorted
reflection no doubt, the probable condition of primitive man. As Sir
John Lubbock and other anthropologists have told us, the intellectual
and moral resemblances between the lowest existing races of mankind and
children are numerous and close.</p>
<p>Yet this way of viewing childhood is not merely of antiquarian interest.
While a monument of<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_32" id="Page_32">[Pg 32]</SPAN></span> his race, and in a manner a key to its history, the
child is also its product. In spite of the fashionable Weismannism of
the hour, there are evolutionists who hold that in the early manifested
tendencies of the child we can discern signs of a hereditary
transmission of the effects of ancestral experiences and activities. His
first manifestations of rage, for example, are a survival of actions of
remote ancestors in their life and death struggles. The impulse of
obedience, which is as much a characteristic of the child as that of
disobedience, may in like manner be regarded as a transmitted rudiment
of a long-practised action of socialized ancestors. This idea of an
increment of intelligence and moral disposition, earned for the
individual not by himself but by his ancestors, has its peculiar
interest. It gives a new meaning to human progress to suppose that the
dawn of infant intelligence, instead of being a return to a primitive
darkness, contains from the first a faint light reflected on it from the
lamp of racial intelligence which has preceded that instead of a return
to the race's starting point, the lowest form of the school of
experience, it is a start in a higher form, the promotion being a reward
conferred on the child for the exertions of his ancestors. Psychological
observation will be well employed in scanning the features of the
infant's mind in order to see whether they yield evidence of such
ancestral dowering.</p>
<p>So much with respect to the rich and varied<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_33" id="Page_33">[Pg 33]</SPAN></span> scientific interest
attaching to the movements of the child's mind. It only remains to touch
on a third main interest in childhood, the practical or educational
interest. The modern world, while erecting the child into an object of
æsthetic contemplation, while bringing to bear on him the bull's eye
lamp of scientific observation, has become sorely troubled by the
momentous problem of rearing him. What was once a matter of instinct and
unthinking rule-of-thumb has become the subject of profound and
perplexing discussion. Mothers—the right sort of mothers that is—feel
that they must know to the core this wee speechless creature which they
are called upon to direct into the safe road to manhood. And
professional teachers, more particularly the beginners in the work of
training, whose work is in some respects the most difficult and the most
honourable, have come to see that a clear insight into child-nature and
its spontaneous movements must precede any intelligent attempt to work
beneficially upon this nature. In this way the teacher has lent his
support to the savant and the psychologist in their investigation of
infancy. More particularly he has betaken him to the psychologist in
order to discover more of the native tendencies and the governing laws
of that unformed child-mind which it is his in a special manner to form.
In addition to this, the growing educational interest in the spontaneous
behaviour of the child's mind may be expected to issue in a demand for<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_34" id="Page_34">[Pg 34]</SPAN></span>
a <i>statistic</i> of childhood, that is to say, carefully arranged
collections of observations bearing on such points as children's
questions, their first thoughts about nature, their manifestations of
sensibility and insensibility.</p>
<p>The awakening in the modern mind of this keen and varied interest in
childhood has led, and is destined to lead still more, to the
observation of infantile ways. This observation will, of course, be of
very different value according as it subserves the contemplation of the
humorous or other æsthetically valuable aspect of child-nature, or as it
is directed towards a scientific understanding of this. Pretty anecdotes
of children which tickle the emotions may or may not add to our insight
into the peculiar mechanism of children's minds. There is no necessary
connection between smiling at infantile drolleries and understanding the
laws of infantile intelligence. Indeed, the mood of merriment, if too
exuberant, will pretty certainly swamp for the moment any desire to
understand.</p>
<p>The observation which is to further understanding, which is to be
acceptable to science, must itself be scientific. That is to say, it
must be at once guided by foreknowledge, specially directed to what is
essential in a phenomenon and its surroundings or conditions, and
perfectly exact. If anybody supposes this to be easy, he should first
try his hand at the work, and then compare what he has seen with what
Darwin or Preyer has been able to discover.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_35" id="Page_35">[Pg 35]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>How difficult this is may be seen even with reference to the outward
physical part of the phenomena to be observed. Ask any mother untrained
in observation to note the first appearance of that complex facial
movement which we call a smile, and you know what kind of result you are
likely to get. The phenomena of a child's mental life, even on its
physical and visible side, are of so subtle and fugitive a character
that only a fine and quick observation is able to cope with them. But
observation of children is never merely seeing. Even the smile has to be
interpreted as a smile by a process of imaginative inference. Many
careless onlookers would say that a baby smiles in the first days from
very happiness, when another and simpler explanation of the movement is
forthcoming. Similarly, it wants much fine judgment to say whether an
infant is merely stumbling accidentally on an articulate sound, or is
imitating your sound. A glance at some of the best memoirs will show how
enormously difficult it is to be sure of a right interpretation of these
early and comparatively simple manifestations of mind.</p>
<p>Things grow a great deal worse when we try to throw our scientific lasso
about the elusive spirit of a child of four or six, and to catch the
exact meaning of its swiftly changing movements. Children are, no doubt,
at this age frank before the eye of love, and their minds are vastly
more accessible than that of the dumb dog that can only look his ardent
thoughts. Yet they are<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_36" id="Page_36">[Pg 36]</SPAN></span> by no means so open to view as is often
supposed. All kinds of shy reticences hamper them: they feel unskilled
in using our cumbrous language; they soon find out that their thoughts
are not as ours, but often make us laugh. And how carefully are they
wont to hide from our sight their nameless terrors, physical and moral.
Much of the deeper childish experience can only reach us, if at all,
years after it is over, through the faulty medium of adult
memory—faulty even when it is the memory of a Goethe, a George Sand, a
Robert Louis Stevenson.</p>
<p>Even when there is perfect candour, and the little one does his best to
instruct us as to what is passing in his mind by his “whys” and his “I
'sposes,” accompanied by the most eloquent of looks, we find ourselves
ever and again unequal to comprehending. Child-thought follows its own
paths—roads, as Mr. Rudyard Kipling has well said, “unknown to those
who have left childhood behind.” The dark sayings of childhood, as when
child asks, “Why am I not somebody else?” will be fully illustrated
below.</p>
<p>This being so, it might well seem arrogant to speak of any “scientific”
investigation of the child's mind; and, to be candid, I may as well
confess that, in spite of some recently published highly hopeful
forecasts of what child-psychology is going to do for us, I think we are
a long way off from a perfectly scientific account of it. Our so-called
theories of children's mental activity have so often been hasty
generalizations from<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_37" id="Page_37">[Pg 37]</SPAN></span> imperfect observation. Children are probably much
more diverse in their ways of thinking and feeling than our theories
suppose. But of this more presently. Even where we meet with a common
and comparatively prominent trait, we are far as yet from having a
perfect comprehension of it. I at least believe that children's play,
about which so much has confidently been written, is but imperfectly
understood. Is it serious business, half-conscious make-believe, more
than half-conscious acting, or, no one of these, or all of them by
turns? I think he would be a bold man who ventured to answer this
question straight away.</p>
<p>In this state of things it might seem well to wait. Possibly by-and-by
we shall light on new methods of tapping the childish consciousness.
Patients in a certain stage of the hypnotic trance have returned, it is
said, to their childish experience and feelings. Some people do this, or
appear to do this, in their dreams. I know a young man who revives vivid
recollections of the experiences of the third year of life when he is
sleepy, and more especially if he is suffering from a cold. These facts
suggest that if we only knew more about the mode of working of the brain
we might reinstate a special group of conditions which would secure a
re-emergence of childish ideas and sentiments.</p>
<p>Yet our case is not so hopeless that we need defer inquiry into the
child's mind until human science has fathomed all the mysteries of the<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_38" id="Page_38">[Pg 38]</SPAN></span>
brain. We can know many things of this mind, and these of great
importance, even now. The naturalist discusses the actions of the lower
animals, confidently attributing intelligent planning here and a germ of
vanity or even of moral sense there; and it would be hard were we
forbidden to study the little people that are of our own race, and are a
thousand times more open to inspection. Really good work has already
been done here, and one should be grateful. At the same time, it seems
to me of the greatest importance to recognize that it is but a
beginning: that the child which the modern world has in the main
discovered is after all only half discovered: that if we are to get at
his inner life, his playful conceits, his solemn broodings over the
mysteries of things, his way of responding to the motley show of life,
we must carry this work of noting and interpreting to a much higher
point.</p>
<p>Now, if progress is to be made in this work, we must have specially
qualified workers. All who know anything of the gross misunderstandings
of children of which many so-called intelligent adults are capable, will
bear me out when I say that a certain gift of penetration is absolutely
indispensable here. If any one asks me what the qualifications of a good
child-observer amount to, I may perhaps answer, for the sake of brevity,
“A divining faculty, the offspring of child-love, perfected by
scientific training.” Let us see what this includes.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_39" id="Page_39">[Pg 39]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>That the observer of children must be a diviner, a sort of clairvoyant
reader of their secret thoughts, seems to me perfectly obvious. Watch
half a dozen men who find themselves unexpectedly ushered into a room
tenanted by a small child, and you will soon be able to distinguish the
diviners, who, just because they have in themselves something akin to
the child, seem able at once to get into touch with children. It is
probable that women's acknowledged superiority in knowledge of
child-nature is owing to their higher gift of sympathetic insight. This
faculty, so far from being purely intellectual, is very largely the
outgrowth of a peculiar moral nature to which the life of all small
things, and of children more than all, is always sweet and congenial. It
is very much of a secondary, or acquired instinct; that is, an
unreflecting intuition which is the outgrowth of a large experience. For
the child-lover seeks the object of his love, and is never so happy as
when associating with children and sharing in their thoughts and their
pleasures. And it is through such habitual intercourse that there forms
itself the instinct or tact by which the significance of childish
manifestation is at once unerringly discerned.</p>
<p>There is in this tact or fineness of spiritual touch one constituent so
important as to deserve special mention. I mean a lively memory of one's
own childhood. As I have observed above, I do not believe in an exact
and trustworthy reproduction in later life of particular incidents<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_40" id="Page_40">[Pg 40]</SPAN></span> of
childhood. All recalling of past experiences illustrates the modifying
influence of the later self in its attempt to assimilate and understand
the past self; and this transforming effect is at its maximum when we
try to get back to childhood. But though our memory of childhood is not
in itself exact enough to furnish facts, it may be sufficiently strong
for the purposes of interpreting our observations of the children we see
about us. It is said, and said rightly, that in order to read a child's
mind we need imagination, and since all imagination is merely
readjustment of individual experience, it follows that the skilled
decipherer of infantile characters needs before all things to be in
touch with his own early feelings and thoughts. And this is just what we
find. The vivacious, genial woman who is never so much at home as when
surrounded by a bevy of eager-minded children is a woman who remains
young in the important sense that she retains much of the freshness and
unconventionality of mind, much of the gaiety and expansiveness of early
life. Conversely one may feel pretty sure that a woman who retains a
vivid memory of her childish ideas and feelings will be drawn to the
companionship of children. After reading their autobiographies one
hardly needs to be told that Goethe carried into old age his quick
responsiveness to the gaiety of the young heart; and that George Sand
when grown old was never so happy as when gathering the youngsters about
her.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_41" id="Page_41">[Pg 41]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>Yet valuable as is this gift of sympathetic insight, it will not, of
course, conduce to that methodical, exact kind of observation which is
required by science. Hence the need of the second qualification:
psychological training. By this is meant that special knowledge which
comes from studying the principles of the science, its peculiar
problems, and the methods appropriate to these, together with the
special skill which is attained by a methodical, practical application
of this knowledge in the actual observation and interpretation of
manifestations of mind. Thus a woman who wishes to observe to good
effect the mind of a child of three must have a sufficient acquaintance
with the general course of the mental life to know what to expect, and
in what way the phenomena observed have to be interpreted. Really fine
and fruitful observation is the outcome of a large knowledge, and
anybody who is to carry out in a scientific fashion the observation of
the humblest phase of a child's mental life must already know this life
as a whole, so far as psychology can as yet describe its
characteristics, and determine the conditions of its activity.</p>
<p>And here the question naturally arises: “Who is to carry out this new
line of scientific observation?” To begin with the first stage of it,
who is to carry out the exact methodical record of the movements of the
infant? It is evident that qualification or capacity is not all that is
necessary here; capacity must be favoured with<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_42" id="Page_42">[Pg 42]</SPAN></span> opportunity before the
work can be actually begun.</p>
<p>It has been pointed out that the pioneers who struck out this new line
of experimental research were medical men. The meaning of this fact is
pretty apparent. The doctor has not only a turn for scientific
observation: he is a privileged person in the nursery. The natural
guardians of infancy, the mother and the nurse, exempt him from their
general ban on the male. He excepted, no man, not even the child's own
father, is allowed to meddle too much with that divine mystery, that
meeting point of all the graces and all the beatitudes, the infant.</p>
<p>Consider for a moment the natural prejudice which the inquirer into the
characteristics of the infant has to face. Such inquiry is not merely
passively watching what spontaneously presents itself; it is
emphatically experimenting, that is, the calling out of reactions by
applying appropriate stimuli. Even to try whether the new-born babe will
close its fingers on your finger when brought into contact with their
anterior surface may well seem impious to a properly constituted nurse.
To propose to test the wee creature's sense of taste by applying drops
of various solutions, as acid, bitters, etc., to the tongue, or to
provoke ocular movements to the right or the left, would pretty
certainly seem a profanation of the temple of infancy, if not fraught
with danger to its tiny deity. And as to trying Dr. Robinson's
experiment of getting<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_43" id="Page_43">[Pg 43]</SPAN></span> the newly arrived visitor to suspend his whole
precious weight by clasping a bar, it is pretty certain that, women
being constituted as at present, only a medical man could have dreamt of
so daring a feat.</p>
<p>There is no doubt that baby-worship, the sentimental adoration of infant
ways, is highly inimical to the carrying out of a perfectly cool and
impartial process of scientific observation. Hence the average mother
can hardly be expected to do more than barely to tolerate this
encroaching of experiment into the hallowed retreat of the nursery. Even
in these days of rapid modification of what used to be thought
unalterable sexual characters, one may be bold enough to hazard the
prophecy that women who have had scientific training will, if they
happen to become mothers, hardly be disposed to give their minds at the
very outset to the rather complex and difficult work, say, of making an
accurate scientific inventory of the several modes of infantile
sensibility, visual, auditory, and so forth, and of the alterations in
these from day to day.</p>
<p>It is for the coarser fibred man, then, to undertake much of the earlier
experimental work in the investigation of child-nature. And if fathers
will duly qualify themselves they will probably find that permission
will little by little be given them to carry out investigations, short,
of course, of anything that looks distinctly dangerous to the little
being's comfort.</p>
<p>At the same time it is evident that a complete<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_44" id="Page_44">[Pg 44]</SPAN></span> series of observations
of the infant can hardly be carried out by a man alone. It is for the
mother, or some other woman with a pass-key to the nursery, with her
frequent and prolonged opportunities of observation to attempt a careful
and methodical register of mental progress. Hence the importance of
enlisting the mother or her female representative as collaborateur or at
least as assistant. Thus supposing the father is bent on ascertaining
the exact dates and the order of appearance of the different articulate
sounds, which is rather a subject of passive observation than of active
experiment; he will be almost compelled to call in the aid of one who
has the considerable advantage of passing a good part of each day near
the child.<SPAN name="FNanchor_1_1" id="FNanchor_1_1"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_1_1" class="fnanchor">[1]</SPAN></p>
<p>As the wee thing grows and its nervous system becomes more stable and
robust more in the way of research may of course be safely attempted. In
this higher stage the work of observation will be less simple and
involve more of special psychological knowledge. It is a comparatively
easy thing to say whether the sudden approach<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_45" id="Page_45">[Pg 45]</SPAN></span> of an object to the eye
of a baby a week or so old calls forth the reflex known as blinking: it
is a much more difficult thing to say what are the preferences of a
child of twelve months in the matter of simple forms, or even colours.</p>
<p>The problem of the order of development of the colour-sense in children
looks at first easy enough. Any mother, it may be thought, can say which
colours the child first recognizes by naming them when seen, or picking
them out when another names them. Yet simple as it looks, the problem is
in reality anything but simple. A German investigator, Professor Preyer
of Berlin, went to work methodically with his little boy of two years in
order to see in what order he would discriminate colours. Two colours,
red and green, were first shown, the name added to each, and the child
then asked: “Which is red?” “Which is green?” Then other colours were
added and the experiments repeated. According to these researches this
particular child first acquired a clear discriminative awareness of
yellow. Preyer's results have not, however, been confirmed by other
investigators, as M. Binet, of Paris, who followed a similar method of
inquiry. Thus according to Binet it is not yellow but blue which carries
the day in the competition for the child's preferential recognition.</p>
<p>What, it may be asked, is the explanation of this? Is it that children
differ in the mode of development of their colour-sensibility to this<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_46" id="Page_46">[Pg 46]</SPAN></span>
extent, or can it be that there is some fault in the method of
investigation? It has been recently suggested that the mode of testing
colour-discrimination by naming is open to the objection that a child
may get hold of one verbal sound as “red” more easily than another as
“green” and that this would facilitate the recognition of the former. If
in this way the recognition of a colour is aided by the retention of its
name, we must get rid of this disturbing element of sound. Accordingly
new methods of experiment have been attempted in France and America.
Thus Professor Baldwin investigates the matter by placing two colours
opposite the child's two arms and noting which is reached out to by
right or left arm, which is ignored. He has tabulated the results of a
short series of these simple experiments for testing childish
preference, and supports the conclusions of Binet, as against those of
Preyer, that blue comes in for the first place in the child's
discriminative recognition.<SPAN name="FNanchor_2_2" id="FNanchor_2_2"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_2_2" class="fnanchor">[2]</SPAN> It is, however, easy to see that this
method has its own characteristic defects. Thus, to begin with, it
evidently does not directly test colour-discrimination at all, but the
liking for or interest in colours, which though it undoubtedly implies a
measure of discrimination must not be confused with this. And even as a
test of preference it is very likely to be misapplied. Thus supposing
that the two colours are not<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_47" id="Page_47">[Pg 47]</SPAN></span> equally bright, then the child will grasp
at one rather than at the other, because it is a brighter object and not
because it is this particular colour. Again if one colour falls more
into the first and fresh period of the exercise when the child is fresh
and active, whereas another falls more into the second period when he is
tired and inactive, the results would, it is evident, give too much
value to the former. Similarly, if one colour were brought in after
longer intervals of time than another it would have more attractive
force through its greater novelty.</p>
<p>Enough has been said to show how very delicate a problem we have here to
deal with. And if scientific men are still busy settling the point how
the problem can be best dealt with, it seems hopeless for the amateur to
dabble in the matter.</p>
<p>I have purposely chosen a problem of peculiar complexity and delicacy in
order to illustrate the importance of that training which makes the
mental eye of the observer quick to analyse the phenomenon to be dealt
with so as to take in all its conditions. Yet there are many parts of
this work of observing the child's mind which do not make so heavy a
demand on technical ability, but can be done by any intelligent observer
prepared for the task by a reasonable amount of psychological study. I
refer more particularly to that rich and highly interesting field of
exploration which opens up when the child begins to talk. It is in the
spontaneous<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_48" id="Page_48">[Pg 48]</SPAN></span> utterances of children, their first quaint uses of words,
that we can best watch the play of the instinctive tendencies of
thought. Children's talk is always valuable to a psychologist; and for
my part I would be glad of as many anecdotal records of their sayings as
I could collect.</p>
<p>Here, then, there seems to be room for a relatively simple and unskilled
kind of observing work. Yet it would be a mistake to suppose that even
this branch of child-observation requires nothing but ordinary
intelligence. To begin with, we are all prone, till by special training
we have learned to check the inclination, to read far too much of our
older thought and sentiment into children. As M. Drox observes, “we are
the dupes of ourselves when we observe the babe.”</p>
<p>Again, there is a subtle source of error connected with the very
attitude of undergoing examination which only a carefully trained
observer of childish ways will avoid. A child is very quick in spying
whether he is being observed, and as soon as he suspects that you are
specially interested in his talk he is apt to try to produce an effect.
This wish to say something startling, wonderful, or what not, will, it
is obvious, detract from the value of the utterance.</p>
<p>But once more the saying which it is so easy to report has had its
history, and the observer who knows something of psychology will look
out for facts, that is to say, experiences of the child, suggestions
made by others' words which throw<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_49" id="Page_49">[Pg 49]</SPAN></span> light on the saying. No fact is
really quite simple, and the reason why some facts look so simple is
that the observer does not include in his view all the connections of
the occurrence which he is inspecting. The unskilled observer of
children is apt to send scraps, fragments of facts, which have not their
natural setting. The value of psychological training is that it makes
one as jealously mindful of wholeness in facts as a housewife of
wholeness in her porcelain. It is, indeed, only when the whole fact is
before us, in well-defined contour, that we can begin to deal with its
meaning. Thus although those ignorant of psychology may assist us in
this region of fact-finding, they can never accomplish that completer
and exacter kind of observation which we dignify by the name of Science.</p>
<p>One may conclude then that women may be fitted to become valuable
labourers in this new field of investigation, if only they will acquire
a genuine scientific interest in babyhood, and a fair amount of
scientific training. That a large number of women will get so far is I
think doubtful: the sentimental or æsthetic attraction of the baby is
apt to be a serious obstacle to a cold matter-of-fact examination of it
as a scientific specimen. The natural delight of a mother in every new
exhibition of infantile wisdom or prowess is liable to blind her to the
exceedingly modest significance of the child's performances as seen from
the scientific point of view. Yet as I have hinted, this very fondness
for infantile<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_50" id="Page_50">[Pg 50]</SPAN></span> ways, may, if only the scientific caution is added, prove
a valuable excitant to study. In England, and in America, there are
already a considerable number of women who have undergone some serious
training in psychology, and it may not be too much to hope that before
long we shall have a band of mothers and aunts busily engaged in noting
and recording the movements of children's minds.</p>
<p>I have assumed here that what is wanted is careful studies of individual
children as they may be approached in the nursery. And these records of
individual children, after the pattern of Preyer's monograph, are I
think our greatest need. We are wont to talk rather too glibly about
that abstraction, “the child,” as if all children rigorously
corresponded to one pattern, of which pattern we have a perfect
knowledge. Mothers at least know that this is not so. Children of the
same family will be found to differ very widely (within the
comparatively narrow field of childish traits), as, for example, in
respect of matter-of-factness, of fancifulness, of inquisitiveness.
Thus, while it is probably true that most children at a certain age are
greedy of the pleasures of the imagination, Nature in her well-known
dislike of monotony has taken care to make a few decidedly
unimaginative. We need to know much more about these variations: and
what will best help us here is a number of careful records of infant
progress, embracing examples not only of different sexes<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_51" id="Page_51">[Pg 51]</SPAN></span> and
temperaments, but also of different social conditions and nationalities.
When we have such a collection of monographs we shall be in a much
better position to fill out the hazy outline of our abstract conception
of childhood with definite and characteristic lineaments.</p>
<p>At the same time I gladly allow that other modes of observation are
possible and in their way useful. This applies to older children who
pass into the collective existence of the school-class. Here something
like collective or statistical inquiry may be begun, as that into the
contents of children's minds, their ignorances and misapprehensions
about common objects. Some part of this inquiry into the minds of school
children may very well be undertaken by an intelligent teacher. Thus it
would be valuable to have careful records of children's progress carried
out by pre-arranged tests, so as to get collections of examples of
mental activity at different ages. More special lines of inquiry having
a truly experimental character might be carried out by experts, as those
already begun with reference to children's “span of apprehension,”
<i>i.e.</i>, the number of digits or nonsense syllables that can be
reproduced after a single hearing, investigations into the effects of
fatigue on mental processes, into the effect of number of repetitions on
the certainty of reproduction, into musical sensitiveness and so forth.</p>
<p>Valuable as such statistical investigation undoubtedly is, it is no
substitute for the careful<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_52" id="Page_52">[Pg 52]</SPAN></span> methodical study of the individual child.
This seems to me the greatest desideratum just now. Since the teacher
needs for practical reasons to make a careful study of individuals he
might well assist here. In these days of literary collaboration it might
not be amiss for a kindergarten teacher to write an account of a child's
mind in co-operation with the mother. Such a record if well done would
be of the greatest value. The co-operation of the mother seems to me
quite indispensable, since even where there is out-of-class intercourse
between teacher and pupil the knowledge acquired by the former never
equals that of the mother.</p>
<div class="footnotes"><h3>FOOTNOTES:</h3>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_1_1" id="Footnote_1_1"></SPAN><SPAN href="#FNanchor_1_1"><span class="label">[1]</span></SPAN>The great advantage which the female observer of the infant's mind
has over her male competitor is clearly illustrated in some recent
studies of childhood by American women. I would especially call
attention to a study by Miss M. W. Shinn, (University of California
series) <i>Notes on the Development of a Child</i> (the writer's niece),
where the minute and painstaking record (e.g. of the child's
colour-discrimination and visual space exploration) points to the ample
opportunity of observation which comes more readily to women.</p>
</div>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_2_2" id="Footnote_2_2"></SPAN><SPAN href="#FNanchor_2_2"><span class="label">[2]</span></SPAN>“Mental Development in the Child and the Race,” chap. III.</p>
</div>
</div>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="TWINS_THEIR_HISTORY_AS_A_CRITERION_OF_THE_RELATIVE_POWERS_OF_NATURE_AND" id="TWINS_THEIR_HISTORY_AS_A_CRITERION_OF_THE_RELATIVE_POWERS_OF_NATURE_AND"></SPAN>TWINS, THEIR HISTORY AS A CRITERION<br/> OF THE RELATIVE POWERS<br/>OF NATURE AND NURTURE</h2>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_53" id="Page_53">[Pg 53]</SPAN></span></p>
<p><span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></p>
</div>
<h3>FRANCIS GALTON</h3>
<div class="noteb"><p>[Francis Galton, a cousin of Charles Darwin, has won eminence
by bringing problems of human development to the test of
statistical inquiry. Among his works are “Hereditary Genius,”
“English Men of Science, Their Nature and Nurture,” “Human
Faculty,” and “Natural Inheritance.” The study of Twins here
presented is taken from “Human Faculty,” published by
Macmillan & Co., London, 1883.]</p>
</div>
<p>The exceedingly close resemblance attributed to twins has been the
subject of many novels and plays, and most persons have felt a desire to
know upon what basis of truth those works of fiction may rest. But twins
have many other claims to attention, one of which will be discussed in
the present memoir. It is, that their history affords means of
distinguishing between the effects of tendencies received at birth, and
of those that were imposed by the circumstances of their after lives; in
other words, between the effects of nature and of nurture. This is a
subject of especial importance in its bearings on investigations into
mental heredity, and I, for my part, have keenly felt the difficulty of
drawing the necessary distinction whenever I tried to estimate<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_54" id="Page_54">[Pg 54]</SPAN></span> the
degree in which mental ability was, on the average, inherited. The
objection to statistical evidence in proof of its inheritance has always
been: “The persons whom you compare may have lived under similar social
conditions and have had similar advantages of education, but such
prominent conditions are only a small part of those that determine the
future of each man's life. It is to trifling accidental circumstances
that the bent of his disposition and his success are mainly due, and
these you leave wholly out of account—in fact, they do not admit of
being tabulated, and therefore your statistics, however plausible at
first sight, are really of very little use.” No method of enquiry which
I have been able to carry out—and I have tried many methods—is wholly
free from this objection. I have therefore attacked the problem from the
opposite side, seeking for some new method by which it would be possible
to weigh in just scales the respective effects of nature and nurture,
and to ascertain their several shares in framing the disposition and
intellectual ability of men. The life history of twins supplies what I
wanted. We might begin by enquiring about twins who were closely alike
in boyhood and youth, and who were educated together for many years, and
learn whether they subsequently grew unlike, and, if so, what the main
causes were which, in the opinion of the family, produced the
dissimilarity. In this way we may obtain much direct evidence of the
kind we want; but we<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_55" id="Page_55">[Pg 55]</SPAN></span> can also obtain yet more valuable evidence by a
converse method. We can enquire into the history of twins who were
exceedingly unlike in childhood, and learn how far they became
assimilated under the influence of their identical nurtures; having the
same home, the same teachers, the same associates, and in every other
respect the same surroundings.</p>
<p>My materials were obtained by sending circulars of enquiry to persons
who were either twins themselves or the near relations of twins. The
printed questions were in thirteen groups; the last of them asked for
the addresses of other twins known to the recipient who might be likely
to respond if I wrote to them. This happily led to a continually
widening circle of correspondence, which I pursued until enough material
was accumulated for a general reconnaissance of the subject.</p>
<p>The reader will easily understand that the word “twins” is a vague
expression, which covers two very dissimilar events; the one
corresponding to the progeny of animals that have usually more than one
young one at a birth, and the other corresponding to those double-yolked
eggs that are due to two germinal spots in a single ovum. The
consequence of this is, that I find a curious discontinuity in my
results. One would have expected that twins would commonly be found to
possess a certain average likeness to one another; that a few would
greatly exceed that degree of likeness, and a few would greatly fall<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_56" id="Page_56">[Pg 56]</SPAN></span>
short of it; but this is not at all the case. Twins may be divided into
three groups, so distinct that there are not many intermediate
instances; namely, strongly alike, moderately alike, and extremely
dissimilar. When the twins are a boy and a girl, they are never closely
alike; in fact, their origin never corresponds to that of the
above-mentioned double-yolked eggs.</p>
<p>I have received about eighty returns of cases of close similarity,
thirty-five of which entered into many instructive details. In a few of
these not a single point of difference could be specified. In the
remainder, the colour of the hair and eyes were almost always identical;
the height, weight, and strength were generally very nearly so, but I
have a few cases of a notable difference in these, notwithstanding the
resemblance was otherwise very near. The manner and address of the
thirty-five pairs of twins is usually described as being very similar,
though there often exists a difference of expression familiar to near
relatives but unperceived by strangers. The intonation of the voice when
speaking is commonly the same, but it frequently happens that the twins
sing in different keys. Most singularly, that one point in which
similarity is rare is the handwriting. I cannot account for this,
considering how strongly handwriting runs in families, but I am sure of
the fact. I have only one case in which nobody, not even the twins
themselves, could distinguish their own notes of lectures, etc.; barely
two or three in which the handwriting<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_57" id="Page_57">[Pg 57]</SPAN></span> was undistinguishable by others,
and only a few in which it was described as closely alike. On the other
hand, I have many in which it is stated to be unlike, and some in which
it is alluded to as the only point of difference.</p>
<p>One of my enquiries was for anecdotes as regards the mistakes made by
near relatives between the twins. They are numerous, but not very varied
in character. When the twins are children, they have commonly to be
distinguished by ribbons tied round their wrist or neck; nevertheless
the one is sometimes fed, physicked, and whipped by mistake for the
other, and the description of these little domestic catastrophes is
usually given to me by the mother, in a phraseology that is somewhat
touching by reason of its seriousness. I have one case in which a doubt
remains whether the children were not changed in their bath, and the
presumed A is not really B, and <i>vice versa</i>. In another case an artist
was engaged on the portraits of twins who were between three and four
years of age; he had to lay aside his work for three weeks, and, on
resuming it, could not tell to which child the respective likenesses he
had in hand belonged. The mistakes are less numerous on the part of the
mother during the boyhood and girlhood of the twins, but almost as
frequent on the part of strangers. I have many instances of tutors being
unable to distinguish their twin pupils. Thus, two girls used regularly
to impose on their music teacher when one of them wanted a whole
holiday; they<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_58" id="Page_58">[Pg 58]</SPAN></span> had their lessons at separate hours, and the one girl
sacrificed herself to receive two lessons on the same day, while the
other one enjoyed herself. Here is a brief and comprehensive account:
“Exactly alike in all, their schoolmasters never could tell them apart;
at dancing parties they constantly changed partners without discovery;
their close resemblance is scarcely diminished by age.” The following is
a typical schoolboy anecdote: Two twins were fond of playing tricks, and
complaints were frequently made; but the boys would never own which was
the guilty one, and the complainants were never certain which of the two
he was. One head master used to say he would never flog the innocent for
the guilty, and another used to flog both. No less than nine anecdotes
have reached me of a twin seeing his or her reflection in a
looking-glass, and addressing it, in the belief it was the other twin in
person. I have many anecdotes of mistakes when the twins were nearly
grown up. Thus: “Amusing scenes occurred at college when one twin came
to visit the other; the porter on one occasion refused to let the
visitor out of the college gates, for, though they stood side by side,
he professed ignorance as to which he ought to allow to depart.”</p>
<p>Children are usually quick in distinguishing between their parents and
his or her twin: but I have two cases to the contrary. Thus, the
daughter of a twin says: “Such was the marvellous similarity of their
features, voice, manner, etc.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_59" id="Page_59">[Pg 59]</SPAN></span> that I remember, as a child, being very
much puzzled, and I think, had my aunt lived much with us, I should have
ended by thinking I had two mothers.” The other, a father of twins,
remarks: “We were extremely alike, and are so at this moment, so much so
that our children up to five and six years old did not know us apart.”</p>
<p>I have four or five instances of doubt during an engagement of marriage.
Thus: “A married first, but both twins met the lady together for the
first time, and fell in love with her there and then. A managed to see
her home and to gain her affection, though B went sometimes courting in
his place, and neither the lady nor her parents could tell which was
which.” I have also a German letter, written in quaint terms, about twin
brothers who married sisters, but could not easily be distinguished by
them. In the well-known novel by Mr. Wilkie Collins of “Poor Miss
Finch,” the blind girl distinguishes the twin she loves by the touch of
his hand, which gives her a thrill that the touch of the other brother
does not. Philosophers have not, I believe, as yet investigated the
conditions of such thrills; but I have a case in which Miss Finch's test
would have failed. Two persons, both friends of a certain twin lady,
told me that she had frequently remarked to them that “kissing her twin
sister was not like kissing her other sisters, but like kissing
herself—her own hand, for example.”</p>
<p>It would be an interesting experiment for<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_60" id="Page_60">[Pg 60]</SPAN></span> twins who were closely alike,
to try how far dogs could distinguish between them by scent.</p>
<p>I have a few anecdotes of strange mistakes made between twins in adult
life. Thus, an officer writes: “On one occasion when I returned from
foreign service my father turned to me and said, 'I thought you were in
London,' thinking I was my brother—yet he had not seen me for nearly
four years—our resemblance was so great.”</p>
<p>The next and last anecdote I shall give is, perhaps, the most remarkable
of those that I have: it was sent me by the brother of the twins, who
were in middle life at the time of its occurrence: “A was again coming
home from India, on leave; the ship did not arrive for some days after
it was due; the twin brother B had come up from his quarters to receive
A, and their old mother was very nervous. One morning A rushed in,
saying, 'Oh, mother, how are you?' Her answer was, 'No, B, it's a bad
joke; you know how anxious I am!' and it was a little time before A
could persuade her that he was the real man.”</p>
<p>Enough has been said to prove that an extremely close personal
resemblance frequently exists between twins of the same sex; and that,
although the resemblance usually diminishes as they grow into manhood
and womanhood, some cases occur in which the resemblance is lessened in
a hardly perceptible degree. It must be borne in mind that the
divergence of development,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_61" id="Page_61">[Pg 61]</SPAN></span> when it occurs, need not be ascribed to the
effect of different nurtures, but that it is quite possible that it may
be due to the appearance of qualities inherited at birth, though
dormant, like gout, in early life. To this I shall recur.</p>
<p>There is a curious feature in the character of the resemblance between
twins, which has been alluded to by a few correspondents: it is well
illustrated by the following quotations. A mother of twins says: “There
seems to be a sort of interchangeable likeness in expression, that often
gave to each the affect of being more like his brother than himself.”
Again, two twin brothers, writing to me, after analysing their points of
resemblance, which are close and numerous, and pointing out certain
shades of difference, add: “These seem to have marked us through life,
though for a while when we were first separated, the one to go to
business, and the other to college, our respective characters were
inverted; we both think that at that time we each ran into the character
of the other. The proof of this consists in our own recollections, in
our correspondence by letter, and in the views which we then took of
matters in which we were interested.” In explanation of this apparent
interchangeableness, we must recollect that no character is simple, and
that in twins who strongly resemble each other every expression in the
one may be matched by a corresponding expression in the other, but it
does not follow that the same expression should be the dominant one in
both<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_62" id="Page_62">[Pg 62]</SPAN></span> cases. Now it is by their dominant expressions that we should
distinguish between the twins; consequently when one twin has
temporarily the expression which is the dominant one in his brother, he
is apt to be mistaken for him. There are also cases where the
development of the two twins is not strictly by equal steps; they reach
the same goal at the same time, but not by identical stages. Thus: A is
born the larger, then B overtakes and surpasses A, the end being that
the twins become closely alike. This process would aid in giving an
interchangeable likeness at certain periods of their growth, and is
undoubtedly due to nature more frequently than to nurture.</p>
<p>Among my thirty-five detailed cases of close similarity, there are no
less than seven in which both twins suffered from some special ailment
or had some exceptional peculiarity. One twin writes that she and her
sister “have both the defect of not being able to come down stairs
quickly, which, however, was not born with them, but came on at the age
of twenty.” Another pair of twins have a slight congenital flexure of
one of the joints of the little finger: it was inherited from a
grandmother, but neither parents, nor brothers, nor sisters show the
least trace of it. In another case, one was born ruptured, and the other
became so at six months old. Two twins at the age of twenty-three were
attacked by toothache, and the same tooth had to be extracted in each
case. There are curious and close<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_63" id="Page_63">[Pg 63]</SPAN></span> correspondences mentioned in the
falling off of the hair. Two cases are mentioned of death from the same
disease; one of which is very affecting. The outline of the story was
that the twins were closely alike and singularly attached, and had
identical tastes; they both obtained Government clerkships, and kept
house together, when one sickened and died of Bright's disease, and the
other also sickened of the same disease and died seven months later.</p>
<p>In no less than nine out of the thirty-five cases does it appear that
both twins are apt to sicken at the same time. This implies so intimate
a constitutional resemblance, that it is proper to give some quotations
in evidence. Thus, the father of two twins says: “Their general health
is closely alike; whenever one of them has an illness the other
invariably has the same within a day or two, and they usually recover in
the same order. Such has been the case with whooping cough, chicken-pox,
and measles; also with slight bilious attacks, which they have
successively. Latterly, they had a feverish attack at the same time.”
Another parent of twins says: “If anything ails one of them, identical
symptoms <i>nearly always</i> appear in the other: this has been singularly
visible in two instances during the last two months. Thus, when in
London, one fell ill with a violent attack of dysentery, and within
twenty-four hours the other had precisely the same symptoms.”</p>
<p>A medical man writes of twins with whom he<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_64" id="Page_64">[Pg 64]</SPAN></span> is well acquainted: “Whilst
I knew them, for a period of two years, there was not the slightest
tendency towards a difference in body or mind; external influences
seemed powerless to produce any dissimilarity.” The mother of two other
twins, after describing how they were ill simultaneously up to the age
of fifteen, adds, that they shed their first milk teeth within a few
hours of each other.</p>
<p>Trousseau has a very remarkable case (in the chapter on Asthma) in his
important work, “Clinique Médicale.” It was quoted at length in the
original French in Mr. Darwin's “Variation Under Domestication,” vol.
ii. p. 252. The following is a translation:</p>
<p>“I attended twin brothers so extraordinarily alike, that it was
impossible for me to tell which was which without seeing them side by
side. But their physical likeness extended still deeper for they had, so
to speak, a yet more remarkable pathological resemblance. Thus, one of
them, whom I saw at the Néothermes at Paris, suffering from rheumatic
ophthalmia, said to me, 'At this instant, my brother must be having an
ophthalmia like mine;' and, as I had exclaimed against such an
assertion, he showed me a few days afterwards a letter just received by
him from his brother, who was at that time at Vienna, and who expressed
himself in these words: 'I have my ophthalmia; you must be having
yours.' However singular this story may appear, the fact is none the
less exact: it has not been told to me by<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_65" id="Page_65">[Pg 65]</SPAN></span> others, but I have seen it
myself; and I have seen other analogous cases in my practice. These
twins were also asthmatic, and asthmatic to a frightful degree. Though
born in Marseilles, they never were able to stay in that town, where
their business affairs required them to go, without having an attack.
Still more strange, it was sufficient for them to get away only as far
as Toulon in order to be cured of the attack caught at Marseilles. They
travelled continually, and in all countries, on business affairs, and
they remarked that certain localities were extremely hurtful to them,
and that in others they were free from all asthmatic symptoms.”</p>
<p>I do not like to pass over here a most dramatic tale in the <i>Psychologie
Morbide</i> of Dr. J. Moreau (de Tours), Médecin de l'Hospice de Bicetre.
Paris, 1859, p. 172. He speaks “of two twin brothers who had been
confined, on account of monomania, at Bicetre.... Physically the two
young men are so nearly alike that the one is easily mistaken for the
other. Morally, their resemblance is no less complete, and is most
remarkable in its details. Thus, their dominant ideas are absolutely the
same. They both consider themselves subject to imaginary persecutions;
the same enemies have sworn their destruction, and employ the same means
to effect it. Both have hallucinations of hearing. They are both of them
melancholy and morose; they never address a word to anybody, and will
hardly answer the questions that others address to them.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_66" id="Page_66">[Pg 66]</SPAN></span> They always
keep apart and never communicate with one another. An extremely curious
fact which has been frequently noted by the superintendents of their
section of the hospital, and by myself, is this: From time to time, at
very irregular intervals of two, three, and many months, without
appreciable cause, and by the purely spontaneous effect of their
illness, a very marked change takes place in the condition of the two
brothers. Both of them, at the same time, and often on the same day,
rouse themselves from their habitual stupor and prostration; they make
the same complaints, and they come of their own accord to the physician,
with an urgent request to be liberated. I have seen this strange thing
occur, even when they were some miles apart, the one being at Bicetre
and the other living at Sainte-Anne.”</p>
<p>Dr. Moreau ranked as a very considerable medical authority, but I cannot
wholly accept this strange story without fuller information. Dr. Moreau
writes it in too off-hand a way to carry the conviction that he had
investigated the circumstances with the sceptic spirit and scrupulous
exactness which so strange a phenomenon would have required. If full and
precise notes of the case exist, they certainly ought to be published at
length. I sent a copy of this passage to the principal authorities among
the physicians to the insane in England, asking if they had ever
witnessed any similar case. In reply, I have received three noteworthy
instances,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_67" id="Page_67">[Pg 67]</SPAN></span> but none to be compared in their exact parallelism with that
just given. The details of these three cases are painful, and it is not
necessary to my general purpose that I should further allude to them.</p>
<p>There is another curious French case of insanity in twins, which was
pointed out to me by Professor Paget, described by Dr. Baume in the
<i>Annales Medico-Psychologiques</i>, 4 série, vol. i., 1863, p. 312, of
which the following is an abstract. The original contains a few more
details, but it is too long to quote: Francois and Martin, fifty years
of age, worked as railroad contractors between Quimper and Châteaulin.
Martin had twice had slight attacks of insanity. On January 15, a box in
which the twins deposited their savings was robbed. On the night of
January 23-4 both Francois (who lodged at Quimper) and Martin (who lived
with his wife and children at St. Lorette, two leagues from Quimper) had
the same dream at the same hour, three A. M., and both awoke with a
violent start, calling out, “I have caught the thief! I have caught the
thief! they are doing injury to my brother!” They were both of them
extremely agitated, and gave way to similar extravagances, dancing and
leaping. Martin sprang on his grandchild, declaring that he was the
thief, and would have strangled him if he had not been prevented: he
then became steadily worse, complained of violent pains in his head,
went out of doors on some excuse, and tried to drown himself in the
River Steir,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_68" id="Page_68">[Pg 68]</SPAN></span> but was forcibly stopped by his son, who had watched and
followed him. He was then taken to an asylum by gendarmes, where he died
in three days. Francois, on his part calmed down on the morning of the
24th, and employed the day in enquiring about the robbery. By a strange
chance he crossed his brother's path at the moment when the latter was
struggling with the gendarmes; then he himself became maddened, giving
way to extravagant gestures and making incoherent proposals (similar to
those of his brother). He then asked to be bled, which was done, and
afterwards, declaring himself to be better, went out on the pretext of
executing some commission, but really to drown himself in the River
Steir, which he actually did, at the very spot where Martin had
attempted to do the same thing a few hours previously.</p>
<p>The next point which I shall mention, in illustration of the extremely
close resemblance between certain twins, is the similarity in the
association of their ideas. No less than eleven out of the thirty-five
cases testify to this. They make the same remarks on the same occasion,
begin singing the same song at the same moment, and so on; or one would
commence a sentence, and the other would finish it. An observant friend
graphically described to me the effect produced on her by two such twins
whom she had met casually. She said: “Their teeth grew alike, they spoke
alike and together, and said the same things, and seemed just like one
person.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_69" id="Page_69">[Pg 69]</SPAN></span>” One of the most curious anecdotes that I have received
concerning this similarity of ideas was that one twin A, who happened to
be at a town in Scotland, bought a set of champagne glasses which caught
his attention, as a surprise for his brother B; while at the same time,
B, being in England, bought a similar set of precisely the same pattern
as a surprise for A. Other anecdotes of a like kind have reached me
about these twins.</p>
<p>The last point to which I shall allude regards the tastes and
dispositions of the thirty-five pairs of twins. In sixteen cases—that
is, in nearly one half of them—these were described as closely similar;
in the remaining nineteen they were much alike, but subject to certain
named differences. These differences belonged almost wholly to such
groups of qualities as these: The one was the more vigorous, fearless,
energetic; the other was gentle, clinging, and timid: or, again, the one
was more ardent, the other more calm and gentle; or again, the one was
the more independent, original, and self-contained; the other the more
generous, hasty, and vivacious. In short the difference was always that
of intensity or energy in one or other of its protean forms: it did not
extend more deeply into the structure of the characters. The more
vivacious might be subdued by ill health, until he assumed the character
of the other; or the latter might be raised by excellent health to that
of the former. The difference is in the key-note, not in the melody.</p>
<p>It follows from what has been said concerning<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_70" id="Page_70">[Pg 70]</SPAN></span> the similar dispositions
of the twins, the similarity in the associations of their ideas, of
their special ailments, and of their illnesses generally, that the
resemblances are not superficial, but extremely intimate. I have only
two cases altogether of a strong bodily resemblance being accompanied by
mental diversity, and one case only of the converse kind. It must be
remembered that the conditions which govern extreme likeness between
twins are not the same as those between ordinary brothers and sisters (I
may have hereafter to write further about this); and that it would be
wholly incorrect to generalize from what has just been said about the
twins, that mental and bodily likeness are invariably co-ordinate; such
being by no means the case.</p>
<p>We are now in a position to understand that the phrase “close
similarity” is no exaggeration, and to realize the value of the evidence
about to be adduced. Here are thirty-five cases of twins who were
“closely alike” in body and mind when they were young, and who have been
reared exactly alike up to their early manhood and womanhood. Since then
the conditions of their lives have changed; what change of conditions
has produced the most variation?</p>
<p>It was with no little interest that I searched the records of the
thirty-five cases for an answer; and they gave an answer that was not
altogether direct, but it was very distinct, and not at all what I had
expected. They showed me that in some cases the resemblance of body and
mind<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_71" id="Page_71">[Pg 71]</SPAN></span> had continued unaltered up to old age, notwithstanding very
different conditions of life; and they showed in the other cases that
the parents ascribed such dissimilarity as there was wholly, or almost
wholly, to some form of illness. In four cases it was scarlet fever; in
one case, typhus; in one, a slight effect was ascribed to a nervous
fever: then I find effects from an Indian climate; from an illness
(unnamed) of nine months' duration; from varicose veins; from a bad
fracture of the leg, which prevented all active exercise afterwards; and
there were three other cases of ill health. It will be sufficient to
quote one of the returns; in this the father writes:</p>
<p>“At birth they were <i>exactly</i> alike, except that one was born with a bad
varicose affection, the effect of which had been to prevent any violent
exercise, such as dancing, or running, and, as she has grown older, to
make her more serious and thoughtful. Had it not been for this
infirmity, I think the two would have been as exactly alike as it is
possible for two women to be, both mentally and physically; even now
they are constantly mistaken for one another.”</p>
<p>In only a very few cases is there some allusion to the dissimilarity
being partly due to the combined action of many small influences, and in
no case is it largely, much less wholly, ascribed to that cause. In not
a single instance have I met with a word about the growing dissimilarity
being due to the action of the firm, free will of one or both of the
twins, which had triumphed over<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_72" id="Page_72">[Pg 72]</SPAN></span> natural tendencies; and yet a large
proportion of my correspondents happen to be clergymen whose bent of
mind is opposed, as I feel assured from the tone of their letters, to a
necessitarian view of life.</p>
<p>It has been remarked that a growing diversity between twins may be
ascribed to the tardy development of naturally diverse qualities; but we
have a right, upon the evidence I have received, to go further than
this. We have seen that a few twins retain their close resemblance
through life; in other words, instances do exist of thorough similarity
of nature, and in these external circumstances do not create
dissimilarity. Therefore, in those cases, where there is a growing
diversity, and where no external cause can be assigned either by the
twins themselves or by their family for it, we may feel sure that it
must be chiefly or altogether due to a want of thorough similarity in
their nature. Nay further, in some cases it is distinctly affirmed that
the growing dissimilarity can be accounted for in no other way. We may
therefore broadly conclude that the only circumstance, within the range
of those by which persons of similar conditions of life are affected,
capable of producing a marked effect on the character of adults, is
illness or some accident which causes physical infirmity. The twins who
closely resembled each other in childhood and early youth, and were
reared under not very dissimilar conditions, either grow unlike through
the development of natural characteristics<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_73" id="Page_73">[Pg 73]</SPAN></span> which had lain dormant at
first, or else they continue their lives, keeping time like two watches,
hardly to be thrown out of accord except by some physical jar. Nature is
far stronger than nurture within the limited range that I have been
careful to assign to the latter.</p>
<p>The effect of illness, as shown by these replies, is great, and well
deserves further consideration. It appears that the constitution of
youth is not so elastic as we are apt to think, but that an attack, say
of scarlet fever, leaves a permanent mark, easily to be measured by the
present method of comparison. This recalls an impression made strongly
on my mind several years ago by the sight of a few curves drawn by a
mathematical friend. He took monthly measurements of the circumference
of his children's heads during the first few years of their lives, and
he laid down the successive measurements on the successive lines of a
piece of ruled paper, by taking the edge of the paper as a base. He then
joined the free ends of the lines, and so obtained a curve of growth.
These curves had, on the whole, that regularity of sweep that might have
been expected, but each of them showed occasional halts, like the
landing places on a long flight of stairs. The development had been
arrested by something, and was not made up for by after growth. Now, on
the same piece of paper my friend had also registered the various
infantile illnesses of the children, and corresponding to each illness
was one of these halts. There<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_74" id="Page_74">[Pg 74]</SPAN></span> remained no doubt in my mind that, if
these illnesses had been warped off, the development of the children
would have been increased by almost the precise amount lost in these
halts. In other words, the disease had drawn largely upon the capital,
and not only on the income, of their constitutions. I hope these remarks
may induce some men of science to repeat similar experiments on their
children of the future. They may compress two years of a child's history
on one side of a ruled half-sheet of foolscap paper if they cause each
successive line to stand for a successive month, beginning from the
birth of the child; and if they mark off the measurements by laying, not
the 0-inch division of the tape against the edge of the pages, but, say,
the 10-inch division—in order to economize space.</p>
<p>The steady and pitiless march of the hidden weaknesses in our
constitutions, through illness to death, is painfully revealed by these
histories of twins. We are too apt to look upon illness and death as
capricious events, and there are some who ascribe them to the direct
effect of supernatural interference, whereas the fact of the maladies of
two twins being continually alike, shows that illness and death are
necessary incidents in a regular sequence of constitutional changes,
beginning at birth, upon which external circumstances have, on the
whole, very small effect. In cases where the maladies of the twins are
continually alike, the clock of life moves regularly on, governed by
internal mechanism.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_75" id="Page_75">[Pg 75]</SPAN></span> When the hand approaches the hour mark, there is a
sudden click, followed by a whirling of wheels; at the culminating
moment, the stroke falls. Necessitarians may derive new arguments from
the life histories of twins.</p>
<p>We will now consider the converse side of our subject. Hitherto we have
investigated cases where the similarity at first was close, but
afterwards became less: now we will examine those in which there was
great dissimilarity at first, and will see how far an identity of
nurture in childhood and youth tended to assimilate them. As has been
already mentioned, there is a large proportion of cases of sharply
contrasted characteristics, both of body and mind, among twins. I have
twenty such cases, given with much detail. It is a fact, that extreme
dissimilarity, such as existed between Esau and Jacob, is a no less
marked peculiarity in twins of the same sex, than extreme similarity. On
this curious point, and on much else in the history of twins, I have
many remarks to make, but this is not the place to make them.</p>
<p>The evidence given by the twenty cases above mentioned is absolutely
accordant, so that the character of the whole may be exactly conveyed by
two or three quotations. One parent says: “They have had <i>exactly the
same nurture</i> from their birth up to the present time; they are both
perfectly healthy and strong, yet they are otherwise as dissimilar as
two boys could be, physically, mentally, and in their emotional
nature.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_76" id="Page_76">[Pg 76]</SPAN></span>” Here is another case: “I can answer most decidedly that the
twins have been perfectly dissimilar in character, habits, and likeness
from the moment of their birth to the present time, though they were
nursed by the same woman, went to school together, and were never
separated till the age of fifteen.” Here again is one more, in which the
father remarks: “They were curiously different in body and mind from
their birth.” The surviving twin (a senior wrangler of Cambridge) adds:
“A fact struck all our school contemporaries, that my brother and I were
complementary, so to speak, in point of ability and disposition. He was
contemplative, poetical, and literary to a remarkable degree, showing
great power in that line. I was practical, mathematical, and linguistic.
Between us we should have made a very decent sort of a man.” I could
quote others just as strong as these, while I have not a single case in
which my correspondents speak of originally dissimilar characters having
become assimilated through identity of nurture. The impression that all
this evidence leaves on the mind is one of some wonder whether nurture
can do anything at all beyond giving instruction and professional
training. It emphatically corroborates and goes far beyond the
conclusions to which we had already been driven by the cases of
similarity. In these, the causes of divergence began to act about the
period of adult life, when the characters had become somewhat fixed; but
here the causes conducive to<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_77" id="Page_77">[Pg 77]</SPAN></span> assimilation began to act from the
earliest moment of the existence of the twins, when the disposition was
most pliant, and they were continuous until the period of adult life.
There is no escape from the conclusion that nature prevails enormously
over nurture when the differences of nurture do not exceed what is
commonly to be found among persons of the same rank of society and in
the same country. My only fear is that my evidence seems to prove too
much and may be discredited on that account, as it seems contrary to all
experience that nurture should go for little. But experience is often
fallacious in ascribing great effects to trifling circumstances. Many a
person has amused himself with throwing bits of stick into a tiny brook
and watching their progress; how they are arrested, first by one chance
obstacle, then by another; and again, how their onward course is
facilitated by a combination of circumstances. He might ascribe much
importance to each of these events, and think how largely the destiny of
the stick has been governed by a series of trifling accidents.
Nevertheless all the sticks succeed in passing down the current, and
they travel, in the long run, at nearly the same rate. So it is with
life in respect to the several accidents which seem to have had a great
effect upon our careers. The one element, which varies in different
individuals, but is constant in each of them, is the natural tendency;
it corresponds to the current in the stream, and invariably asserts
itself. More<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_78" id="Page_78">[Pg 78]</SPAN></span> might be added on this matter, and much might be said in
qualification of the broad conclusions to which we have arrived, as to
the points in which education appears to create the most permanent
effect; how far by training the intellect and how far by subjecting the
boy to a higher or lower tone of public opinion; but this is foreign to
my immediate object. The latter has been to show broadly, and, I trust,
convincingly, that statistical estimation of natural gifts by a
comparison of successes in life, is not open to the objection stated at
the beginning of this memoir. We have only to take reasonable care in
selecting our statistics, and then we may safely ignore the many small
differences in nurture which are sure to have characterized each
individual case.</p>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="SIGHT_IN_SAVAGES" id="SIGHT_IN_SAVAGES"></SPAN>SIGHT IN SAVAGES</h2>
<div class="center">From “Idle Days in Patagonia”</div>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_79" id="Page_79">[Pg 79]</SPAN></span></p>
<p><span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></p>
</div>
<h3>WILLIAM HENRY HUDSON</h3>
<div class="noteb">[William Henry Hudson was born and for many years resided in
Patagonia. His “The Naturalist in La Plata” and “Idle Days in
Patagonia,” both published by J. M. Dent & Co., London, and
D. Appleton & Co., New York, are among the most delightful
books of natural history ever written.]</div>
<p>A person much given to card-playing once informed me that always after
the first few rounds of a game he knew some of the cards in the pack,
and could recognize them as they were being dealt out, by means of
certain slight shades of difference in the colouring of the backs. He
had turned his attention to this business when very young, and as he was
close upon fifty when he imparted this interesting piece of information,
and had always existed comfortably on his winnings, I saw no reason to
disbelieve what he told me. Yet this very man, whose vision was keen
enough to detect differences in cards so slight that another could not
see them, even when pointed out—this preternaturally sharp-eyed
individual was greatly surprised when I explained to him that
half a dozen birds of the sparrow kind, that fed in his courtyard, and
sang<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_80" id="Page_80">[Pg 80]</SPAN></span> and built their nests in his garden and vineyard and fields, were
not one but six distinct species. He had never seen any difference in
them: they all had the same customs, the same motions; in size, colour,
and shape they were all one; to his hearing they all chirped and
twittered alike, and warbled the same song.</p>
<p>And as it was with this man, so, to some extent, it is with all of us.
That special thing which interests us, and in which we find our profit
or pleasure, we see very distinctly, and our memories are singularly
tenacious of its image; while other things, in which we take only a
general interest, or which are nothing to us, are not seen so sharply,
and soon become blurred in memory; and if there happens to be a pretty
close resemblance in several of them, as in the case of my gambling
friend's half a dozen sparrows, which, like snowflakes, were “seen
rather than distinguished,” this indistinctness of their images on the
eye and the mind causes them all to appear alike. We have, as it were,
two visions—one to which all objects appear vividly and close to us,
and are permanently photographed on the mind; the other which sees
things at a distance, and with that indistinctness of outline and
uniformity of colour which distance gives.</p>
<p>In this place I had proposed to draw on my La Plata notebooks for some
amusing illustrations of this fact of our two sights; but it is not
necessary to go so far afield for illustrations, or<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_81" id="Page_81">[Pg 81]</SPAN></span> to insist on a
thing so familiar. “The shepherd knows his sheep,” is a saying just as
true of this country—of Scotland, at all events—as of the far East.
Detectives, also military men who take an interest in their profession,
see faces more sharply than most people, and remember them as distinctly
as others remember the faces of a very limited number of individuals—of
those they love or fear or constantly associate with. Sailors see
atmospheric changes which are not apparent to others; and, in like
manner, the physician detects the signs of malady in faces which to the
uninstructed vision seem healthy enough. And so on through the whole
range of professions and pursuits which men have: each person inhabits a
little world of his own, as it were, which to others is only part of the
distant general blueness obscuring all things, but in which, to him,
every object stands out with wonderful clearness, and plainly tells its
story.</p>
<p>All this may sound very trite, very trivial and matter of common
knowledge—so common as to be known to every schoolboy and to the boy
that goeth not to school; yet it is because this simple familiar fact
has been ignored, or has not always been borne in mind by our masters,
that they have taught us an error, namely, that savages are our
superiors in visual power, and that the difference is so great that ours
is a dim decaying sense compared with their brilliant faculty, and that
only when we survey the prospect through powerful field-glasses do we
rise to<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_82" id="Page_82">[Pg 82]</SPAN></span> their level and see the world as they see it. The truth is that
the savage sight is no better than ours, although it might seem natural
enough to think the contrary, on account of their simple natural life in
the desert, which is always green and restful to the eye, or supposed to
be so; and because they have no gas nor even candlelight to irritate the
visual nerve, and do themselves no injury by poring over miserable
books.</p>
<p>Possibly, then, the beginning of the error was in this preconceived
notion, that greenness and the absence of artificial light, with other
conditions of a primitive life, kept the sight from deteriorating. The
eye's adaptiveness did not get sufficient credit. We know how the
muscles may be developed by training, that the blacksmith and
prizefighter have mightier arms than others; but it was perhaps assumed
that the complex structure and extreme delicacy of the eye would make it
less adaptive than other and coarser organs. Whatever the origin of the
error may have been, it is certain that it has received the approval of
scientists, and that they never open their lips on the subject except to
give it fresh confirmation. Their researches have brought to light a
great variety of eye-troubles, which, in many cases, are not troublesome
at all, until they are discovered, named with a startling name and
described in terms very alarming to persons of timid character.
Frequently they are not maladies, but inherited defects, like bandy
legs, prominent teeth,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_83" id="Page_83">[Pg 83]</SPAN></span> crushed toes, tender skin and numberless other
malformations. That such eye-defects are as common among savages as
among ourselves, I do not say, and to this matter I shall return later
on; but until the eyes of savages are scientifically examined, it seems
a very bold thing to say that defective colour-sense is due to the
inimical conditions of our civilization; for we know as little about the
colour-sense of savages as we do about the colour-sense of the old
Greeks. That the savage sight is vastly more powerful than ours was
perhaps not so bold a thing to say, seeing that in this matter our
teachers were misled by travellers' tales, and perhaps by other
considerations, as, for instance, the absence of artificial aids to
sight among the children of nature. The redskin may be very old, but as
he sits sunning himself before his wigwam in the early morning he is
never observed to trombone his newspaper.</p>
<p>The reader may spare himself the trouble of smiling, for this is not
mere supposition; in this case observation came first and reflection
afterwards, for I happen to know something of savages from experience,
and when they were using their eyes in their way and for their purposes,
I used mine for my purpose, which was different. It is true that the
redskin will point you out an object in the distance and tell its
character, and it will be to your sight only a dark-coloured object,
which might be a bush, or stone, or animal of some large kind, or even a
house. The secret<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_84" id="Page_84">[Pg 84]</SPAN></span> of the difference is that his eye is trained and
accustomed to see certain things, which he looks for and expects to
find. Put him where the conditions are new to him and he will be at
fault; or even on his native heath, set before him an unfamiliar or
unexpected object, and he will show no superiority over his civilized
brother. I have witnessed one instance in which not one but five men
were all at fault and made a wrong guess; while the one person of our
party who guessed correctly, or saw better perhaps, was a child of
civilization and a reader of books, and, what is perhaps even more, the
descendant of a long line of bookish men. This amazed me at the moment,
for until then my childlike faith in the ideas of Humboldt and of the
world generally on the subject had never been disturbed. Now I see how
this curious thing happened. The object was at such a distance that to
all of us alike it presented no definite form, but was merely something
dark, standing against a hoary background of tall grass-plumes. Our
guides, principally regarding its size, at once guessed it to be an
animal which they no doubt expected to find in that place—namely, a
wild horse. The other, who did not have that training of the eye and
mind for distant objects in the desert which is like an instinct, and,
like instinct, is liable to mistakes, and who carefully studied its
appearance for himself, pronounced it to be a dark bush. When we got
near it turned out to be a clump of tall bulrushes, growing in a<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_85" id="Page_85">[Pg 85]</SPAN></span> place
where they had no business to grow, and burnt by drought and frosts to
so dark a brown that at a distance they seemed quite black.</p>
<p>In the following case the savage was right. I pointed out an object,
dark, far off, so low down as to be just visible above the tall grasses,
passing with a falling and rising motion like that of a horseman going
at a swinging gallop. “There goes a mounted man,” I remarked. “No—a
traru,” returned my companion, after one swift glance; the traru being a
large, black, eagle-like bird of the plains. But the object was not
necessarily more distinct to him than to me; he could not see wings and
beak at that distance; but the traru was a familiar object, which he was
accustomed to see at all distances—a figure in the landscape which he
looked for and expected to find. It was only a dark blot on the horizon;
but he knew the animal's habits and appearance, and that when seen far
off, in its low down, dilatory rising and falling flight, it simulates
the appearance of a horseman in full gallop. To know this and a few
other things was his vocation. If one had set him to find a reversed
little <i>s</i> in the middle of a closely-printed page the tears would have
run down his bronzed cheeks, and he would have abandoned the vain quest
with aching eyeballs. Yet the proofreader can find the little <i>s</i> in a few
moments, without straining his sight. But it is infinitely more
important to the savage than to us to see things quickly and guess their
nature correctly.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_86" id="Page_86">[Pg 86]</SPAN></span> His daily food, the recovery of his lost animals and
his personal safety depend on it; and it is not, therefore, strange that
every blot of dark colour, every moving and motionless object on the
horizon tells its story better to him than to a stranger; especially
when we consider how small a variety of objects he is called on to see
and judge of in the level monotonous region he inhabits.</p>
<p>This quick judging of dimly seen distant things, the eye and mind
achievement of the mounted barbarian on the unobstructed plains, is not
nearly so admirable as that of his fellow-savage in sub-tropical regions
overspread with dense vegetation, with animal life in great abundance
and variety and where half the attention must be given to species
dangerous to man, often very small in size. In some hot humid forest
districts, the European who should attempt to hunt or explore with bare
feet and legs would be pricked or lacerated at almost every step of his
progress, and probably get bitten by a serpent before the day's end. Yet
the Indian passes his life there and, naked or half-naked, explores the
unknown wilderness of thorns and has only his arrows to provide food for
himself and his wife and children. He does not get pierced with thorns
and bitten by serpents, because his eye is nicely trained to pick them
out in time to save himself. He walks rapidly, but he knows every shade
of green, every smooth and crinkled leaf in that dense<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_87" id="Page_87">[Pg 87]</SPAN></span> tangle, full of
snares and deceptions, through which he is obliged to walk; and much as
leaf resembles leaf, he sets his foot where he can safely set it, or,
quickly choosing between two evils, where the prickles and thorns are
tenderest, or, for some reason known to him, hurt least. In like manner
he distinguishes the coiled-up venomous snake, although it lies so
motionless—a habit common to the most deadly kinds—and in its dull
imitative colouring is so difficult to be distinguished on the brown
earth, and among gray sticks and sere and variegated leaves.</p>
<p>A friend of mine, Fontana of Buenos Ayres, who has a life-long
acquaintance with the Argentine Indians, expresses the opinion that at
the age of twelve years the savage of the Pampas has completed his
education and is thereafter able to take care of himself; but that the
savage of the Gran Chaco—the sub-tropical Argentine territory bordering
on Paraguay and Bolivia,—if left to shift for himself at that age would
speedily perish, since he is then only in the middle of his long,
difficult and painful apprenticeship. It was curious and pitiful, he
says, to see the little Indian children in the Chaco, when their skins
were yet tender, stealing away from their mother and trying to follow
the larger ones playing at a distance. At every step they would fall and
get pricked with thorns or cut with sharp-edged rushes and tangled in
the creepers, and hurt and crying they would struggle on and<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_88" id="Page_88">[Pg 88]</SPAN></span> in this
painful manner at last learn where to set their feet.</p>
<p>The snake on the ground, coloured like the ground and shaped like the
dead curved sticks or vines seen everywhere on the ground, and
motionless like the vine, does not more closely assimilate to its
surroundings than birds in trees often do—the birds which the Indian
must also see. A stranger in these regions, even the naturalist with a
sight quickened by enthusiasm, finds it hard to detect a parrot in a
lofty tree, even when he knows that parrots are there; for their
greenness in the green foliage and the correlated habit they possess of
remaining silent and motionless in the presence of an intruder, make
them invisible to him, and he is astonished that the Indian should be
able to detect them. The Indian knows how to look for them; it is his
trade, which is long to learn; but he is obliged to learn it, for his
success in life, and even life itself, depends on it, since in the
savage state Nature kills those who fail in her competitive
examinations.</p>
<p>The reader has doubtless often seen those little picture-puzzles,
variously labelled “Where's the Cat?” or “Mad Bull,” or “Burglar,” or
“Policeman,” or “Snake in the Grass,” etc., in which the thing named and
to be discovered is formed by branches and foliage and by running water
and drapery and lights and shadows in the sketch. At first one finds it
extremely difficult to detect this picture within a picture;<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_89" id="Page_89">[Pg 89]</SPAN></span> and at
last, with the suddenness with which one invariably detects a
dull-coloured snake, seen previously but not distinguished—the object
sought for appears, and is thereafter so plain to the eye that one
cannot look at the sketch, even held at a distance, without seeing the
cat or policeman, or whatever it happens to be. And after patiently
studying some scores or hundreds of these puzzles one gets to know just
how to find the thing concealed, and finds it quickly—almost at a
glance at last. Now, the ingenious person that first invented this
pretty puzzle probably had no thought of Nature, with her curious
imitative and protective resemblances, in his mind; yet he might very
well have taken the hint from Nature, for this is what she does. The
animal that must be seen to be avoided, and the animal that must be seen
to be taken, are there in her picture, sketched in with such cunning art
that to the uninstructed eye they form only portions of branch and
foliage and shadow and sunlight above, and dull-hued or variegated earth
and stones and dead and withering herbage underneath.</p>
<p>It is possible that slight differences may exist in the seeing powers of
different nations, due to the effect of physical conditions: thus, the
inhabitants of mountainous districts and of dry elevated tablelands may
have a better sight than dwellers in low, humid and level regions,
although just the reverse may be the case. Among European nations the
Germans are generally<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_90" id="Page_90">[Pg 90]</SPAN></span> supposed to have weak eyes, owing, some imagine,
to their excessive indulgence in tobacco, while others attribute the
supposed decay to the form of type used in their books, which requires
closer looking at than ours in reading. That they will deteriorate still
further in this direction, and from being a spectacled people become a
blind one, to the joy of their enemies, is not likely to happen, and
probably the decadence has been a great deal exaggerated. Animals living
in darkness become near-sighted, and then nearer-sighted still and so on
progressively until the vanishing point is reached. In a community or
nation a similar decline might begin from much reading of German books,
or perpetual smoking of pipes with big china bowls, or from some other
unknown cause; but the decay could not progress far, because there is
nothing in man to take the place of sight, as there is in the blind cave
rats and fishes and insects. And if we could survey mankind from China
to Peru with all the scientific appliances which are brought to bear on
the Board-school children in London and on the nation generally, the
differences in the powers of vision in the various races, nations and
tribes would probably appear very insignificant. The mistake which eye
specialists and writers on the eye make is that they think too much
about the eye. When they affirm that the conditions of our civilization
are highly injurious to the sight, do they mean all the million
conditions or sets of conditions embraced by our system, with the<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_91" id="Page_91">[Pg 91]</SPAN></span>
infinite variety of occupations and modes of living which men have, from
the lighthouse-keeper to the worker underground, whose day is the dim
glimmer of a miner's lamp? “An organ exercised beyond its wont will grow
and thus meet increase of demand by increase of supply,” Herbert Spencer
says; but, he adds, there is a limit soon reached, beyond which it is
impossible to go. This increase of demand with us is everywhere—now on
this organ and now on that, according to our work and way of life, and
the eye is in no worse case than the other organs. There are among us
many cases of heart complaint; civilization, in such cases, has put too
great a strain on that organ, and it has reached the limit beyond which
it cannot go. And so with the eye. The total number of the defective
among us is no doubt very large, for we know that our system of life
retards—it cannot effectually prevent—the healthy action of natural
selection. Nature pulls one way and we pull the other, compassionately
trying to save the unfit from the consequences of their unfitness. The
humane instinct compels us; but the cruel instinct of the savage, who
hates the sick and the unfit as the inferior animals do, is less painful
to contemplate than that mistaken or perverted compassion which seeks to
perpetuate unfitness, and in the interest of suffering individuals
inflicts a lasting injury on the race.</p>
<p>Pelleschi, in his admirable book on the Chaco Indians, says that
malformations are never seen<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_92" id="Page_92">[Pg 92]</SPAN></span> in these savages, that physically they are
all perfect men; and he remarks that in their exceedingly hard struggle
for existence in a thorny wilderness, beset with perils, any bodily
defect or ailment would be fatal. And as the eye in their life is the
most important organ, it must be an eye without flaw. In this
circumstance only do savages differ from us—namely, in the absence or
rarity of defective eyes among them; and when those who, like Mr.
Brudenell Carter, believe in the decadence of the eye in civilized man
quote Humboldt's words about the miraculous sight of South American
savages, they quote an error. It is not strange that Humboldt should
have fallen into it, for, after all, he had only the means which we all
possess of finding out things—a limited sight and a fallible mind. Like
the savage, he had trained his faculties to observe and infer, and his
inferences like those of the savages, were sometimes wrong.</p>
<p>The savage sight is no better than ours for the simple reason that a
better is not required. Nature has given to him, as to all her
creatures, only what was necessary and nothing for ostentation. Standing
on the ground, his horizon is a limited one; and the animals he preys
on, if often sharper-eyed and swifter than he, are without intelligence,
and thus things are made equal. He can see the rhea as far as the rhea
can see him; and if he possessed the eagle's far-seeing faculty it would
be of no advantage to him. The high-soaring eagle requires to see very
far,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_93" id="Page_93">[Pg 93]</SPAN></span> but the low-flying owl is near-sighted. And so on through the
whole animal world: each kind has sight sufficient to find its food and
escape from its enemies, and nothing beyond. Animals that live close to
the surface have a very limited sight. Moreover, other faculties may
usurp the eye's place, or develop so greatly as to make the eye of only
secondary importance as an organ of intelligence. The snake offers a
curious case. No other sense seems to have developed in it, yet I take
the snake to be one of the nearest-sighted creatures in existence. From
long observation of them I am convinced that small snakes of very
sluggish habits do not see distinctly farther than from one to three
yards. But the snake is the champion faster in the animal world and can
afford to lie quiescent until the wind of chance blows something eatable
in its way; hence it does not require to see an object distinctly until
almost within striking distance. Another remarkable case is that of the
armadillo. Of two species I can confidently say that, if they are not
blind, they are next door to blindness; yet they are diurnal animals
that go abroad in the full glare of noon and wander far in search of
food. But their sense of smell is marvellously acute, and, as in the
case of the mole, it has made sight superfluous. To come back to man:
if, in a state of nature, he is able to guess the character of objects
nine times in ten, or nineteen in twenty, seen as far off as he requires
to see anything, his intellectual faculties<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_94" id="Page_94">[Pg 94]</SPAN></span> make a better sight
unnecessary. If the armadillo's scent had not been so keen and man had
not been gifted with nimble brains, the sight in both cases would have
been vastly stronger; but the sharpening of its sense of smell has
dimmed the armadillo's eyes and made him blinder than a snake; while man
(from no fault of his own) is unable to see farther than the wolf and
the ostrich and the wild ass.</p>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="MECHANISM_IN_THOUGHT_AND_MORALS" id="MECHANISM_IN_THOUGHT_AND_MORALS"></SPAN>MECHANISM IN THOUGHT AND MORALS</h2>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_95" id="Page_95">[Pg 95]</SPAN></span></p>
<span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></div>
<h3>DR. OLIVER WENDELL HOLMES</h3>
<div class="noteb">[Dr. Holmes was at once a distinguished physician, poet,
novelist, and wit. His “Autocrat of the Breakfast Table” is
one of the most charming books ever written, his poetry and
essays are of even greater popularity. Dr. Holmes's Works are
published in fourteen volumes by Houghton, Mifflin & Co.,
Boston and New York, copyright in various editions. The essay
from which extracts follow is in the eighth volume.]</div>
<p>Do we ever think without knowing that we are thinking? The question may
be disguised so as to look a little less paradoxical. Are there any
mental processes of which we are unconscious at the time, but which we
recognize as having taken place by finding certain results in our minds?</p>
<p>That there are such unconscious mental actions is laid down in the
strongest terms by Leibnitz, whose doctrine reverses the axiom of
Descartes into <i>I am, therefore I think</i>. The existence of unconscious
thought is maintained by him in terms we might fairly call audacious,
and illustrated by some of the most striking facts bearing upon it. The
“insensible perceptions,” he says, are as important in pneumatology
[spiritual philosophy] as corpuscles are in physics.—It does not
follow, he says again, that, because<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_96" id="Page_96">[Pg 96]</SPAN></span> we do not perceive thought, it
does not exist.—Something goes on in the mind which answers to the
circulation of the blood and all the internal movements of the
viscera.—In one word, it is a great source of error to believe that
there is no perception in the mind but those of which it is conscious.</p>
<p>This is surely a sufficiently explicit and peremptory statement of the
doctrine, which, under the names of “latent consciousness,” “obscure
perceptions,” “the hidden soul,” “unconscious cerebration,” “reflex
action of the brain,” has been of late years emerging into general
recognition in treatises of psychology and physiology.</p>
<p>His allusion to the circulation of the blood and the movements of the
viscera, as illustrating his paradox of thinking without knowing it,
shows that he saw the whole analogy of the mysterious intellectual
movement with that series of reflex actions so fully described half a
century later by Hartley, whose observations, obscured by wrong
interpretation of the cerebral structure and an insufficient theory of
vibrations which he borrowed from Newton, are yet a remarkable
anticipation of many of the ideas of modern physiology, for which credit
has been given so liberally to Unzer and Prochaska. Unconscious activity
is the rule with the actions most important to life. The lout who lies
stretched on the tavern bench, with just mental activity enough to keep
his pipe from going out, is the unconscious tenant of a laboratory where
such<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_97" id="Page_97">[Pg 97]</SPAN></span> combinations are being constantly made as never Wöhler or
Berthelot could put together; where such fabrics are woven, such colours
dyed, such problems of mechanism solved, such a commerce carried on with
the elements and forces of the outer universe, that the industries of
all the factories and trading establishments in the world are mere
indolence and awkwardness and unproductiveness compared to the
miraculous activities of which his lazy bulk is the unheeding centre.
All these unconscious or reflex actions take place by a mechanism never
more simply stated than in the words of Hartley, as “<i>vibrations</i> which
ascend up the sensory nerves first, and then are detached down the
motory nerves, which communicate with these by some common trunk,
plexus, [network] or ganglion [knot].” The doctrine of Leibnitz, that
the brain may sometimes act without our taking cognizance of it, as the
heart commonly does, as many internal organs always do, seems almost to
belong to our time. The readers of Hamilton and Mill, of Abercrombie,
Laycock and Maudsley, of Sir John Herschel, of Carpenter, of Lecky, of
Dallas, will find many variations on the text of Leibnitz, some new
illustrations, a new classification and nomenclature of the facts; but
the root of the matter is all to be found in his writings.</p>
<p>I will give some instances of work done in the underground workshop of
thought—some of them familiar to the readers of the authors just
mentioned. We wish to remember something<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_98" id="Page_98">[Pg 98]</SPAN></span> in the course of conversation.
No effort of the will can reach it; but we say, “Wait a minute, and it
will come to me,” and go on talking. Presently, perhaps some minutes
later, the idea we are in search of comes all at once into the mind,
delivered like a prepaid bundle, laid at the door of consciousness like
a foundling in a basket. How it came there we know not. The mind must
have been at work groping and feeling for it in the dark: it cannot have
come of itself. Yet, all the while, our consciousness, so far as we are
conscious of our consciousness, was busy with other thoughts.</p>
<p>In old persons, there is sometimes a long interval of obscure mental
action before the answer to a question is evolved. I remember making an
inquiry of an ancient man, whom I met on the road in a waggon with his
daughter, about a certain old burial-ground which I was visiting. He
seemed to listen attentively; but I got no answer. “Wait half a minute
or so,” the daughter said, “and he will tell you.” And sure enough,
after a little time he answered me and to the point. The delay here,
probably, corresponded to what machinists call “lost time,” or “back
lash” in turning an old screw, the thread of which is worn. But, within
a fortnight, I examined a young man for his degree in whom I noticed a
certain regular interval, and a pretty long one, between every question
and its answer. Yet the answer was, in almost every instance, correct,
when at last it did come. It was an<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_99" id="Page_99">[Pg 99]</SPAN></span> idiosyncrasy, I found, which his
previous instructors had noticed. I do not think the mind knows what it
is doing in the interval, in such cases. This latent period, during
which the brain is obscurely at work, may, perhaps, belong to
mathematicians more than others. Swift said of Sir Isaac Newton that, if
one were to ask him a question, “he would revolve it in a circle in his
brain, round and round and round” (the narrator here describing a circle
on his own fore-head), “before he could produce an answer.”</p>
<p>I have often spoken of the same trait in a distinguished friend of my
own, remarkable for his mathematical genius, and compared his sometimes
long-deferred answer to a question with half a dozen others stratified
over it, to the thawing out of the frozen words as told of by Baron
Munchausen and Rabelais, and nobody knows how many others before them.</p>
<p>I was told, within a week, of a business man in Boston, who, having an
important question under consideration, had given it up for the time as
too much for him. But he was conscious of an action going on in his
brain which was so unusual and painful as to excite his apprehensions
that he was threatened with palsy, or something of that sort. After some
hours of this uneasiness, his perplexity was all at once cleared up by
the natural solution of his doubt coming to him—worked out, as he
believed, in that obscure and troubled interval.</p>
<p>The cases are numerous where questions have<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_100" id="Page_100">[Pg 100]</SPAN></span> been answered, or problems
solved, in dreams, or during unconscious sleep. Two of our most
distinguished professors in this institution have had such an
experience, as they tell me; and one of them has often assured me that
he never dreams. Somnambulism and double-consciousness offer another
series of illustrations. Many of my audience remember a murder case,
where the accused was successfully defended, on the ground of
somnambulism, by one of the most brilliant of American lawyers. In the
year 1686 a brother of Lord Culpepper was indicted at the Old Bailey for
shooting one of the guards and acquitted on the same ground of
somnambulism; that is an unconscious and, therefore, irresponsible state
of activity.</p>
<p>A more familiar instance of unconscious action is to be found in what we
call “absent” persons—those who, while wide awake, act with an apparent
purpose, but without really knowing what they are doing; as in La
Bruyère's character, who threw his glass of wine into the backgammon
board and swallowed the dice.</p>
<p>There are a vast number of movements which we perform with perfect
regularity while we are thinking of something quite
different—“automatic actions of the secondary kind,” as Hartley calls
them, and of which he gives various examples. The old woman knits; the
young woman stitches, or perhaps plays her piano and yet talks away as
if nothing but her tongue were busy. Two lovers stroll along side by
side, just born<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_101" id="Page_101">[Pg 101]</SPAN></span> into the rosy morning of their new life, prattling the
sweet follies worth all the wisdom that years will ever bring them. How
much do they think about that wonderful problem of balanced progression
which they solve anew at every step?</p>
<p>We are constantly finding results of unperceived mental processes in our
consciousness. Here is a striking instance, which I borrow from a recent
number of an English journal. It relates to what is considered the most
interesting period of incubation in Sir William Rowan Hamilton's
discovery of quaternions. The time was the 15th of October, 1843. On
that day, he says in a letter to a friend, he was walking from his
observatory to Dublin with Lady Hamilton, when, on reaching Brougham
Bridge, he “felt the galvanic circle of thought close; and the sparks
that fell from it were the fundamental relations between i, j, k,” just
as he used them ever afterwards.</p>
<p>Still another instance of the spontaneous evolution of thought we may
find in the experience of a great poet. When Goethe shut his eyes and
pictured a flower to himself, he says that it developed itself before
him in leaves and blossoms. The result of the mental process appeared as
pictured thought; but the process itself was automatic and
imperceptible.</p>
<p>There are thoughts that never emerge into consciousness, which yet make
their influence felt among the perceptible mental currents, just as the
unseen planets sway the movements of<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_102" id="Page_102">[Pg 102]</SPAN></span> those which are watched and mapped
by the astronomer. Old prejudices that are ashamed to confess themselves
nudge our talking thought to utter their magisterial veto. In hours of
languor, as Mr. Lecky has remarked in his “History of Rationalism,” the
beliefs and fancies of obsolete conditions are apt to take advantage of
us. We know very little of the contents of our minds until some sudden
jar brings them to light, as an earthquake that shakes down a miser's
house brings out the old stockings full of gold and all the hoards that
have been hidden away in holes and crannies.</p>
<p>We not rarely find our personality doubled in our dreams and do battle
with ourselves, unconscious that we are our own antagonists. Dr. Johnson
dreamed that he had a contest of wit with an opponent, and got the worst
of it: of course he furnished the wit for both. Tartini heard the Devil
play a wonderful sonata and set it down on waking. Who was the Devil but
Tartini himself? I remember, in my youth, reading verses in a dream,
written, as I thought, by a rival fledgling of the Muse. They were so
far beyond my powers that I despaired of equalling them; yet I must have
made them unconsciously as I read them. Could I only have remembered
them waking!</p>
<p>But I must here add another personal experience, of which I will say
beforehand—somewhat as honest Isaak Walton said of his pike, “This dish
of meat is too good for any but anglers or honest<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_103" id="Page_103">[Pg 103]</SPAN></span> men”—this story is
good only for philosophers and very small children. I will merely hint
to the former class of thinkers, that its moral bears on two points:
first, the value of our self-estimate, sleeping—possibly, also, waking;
secondly, the significance of general formulæ when looked at in certain
exalted mental conditions.</p>
<p>I once inhaled a pretty full dose of ether, with the determination to
put on record, at the earliest moment of regaining consciousness, the
thought I should find uppermost in my mind. The mighty music of the
triumphal march into nothingness reverberated through my brain, and
filled me with a sense of infinite possibilities, which made me an
archangel for the moment. The veil of eternity was lifted. The one great
truth which underlies all human experience and is the key to all the
mysteries that philosophy has sought in vain to solve, flashed upon me
in a sudden revelation. Henceforth all was clear: a few words had lifted
my intelligence to the level of the knowledge of the cherubim. As my
natural condition returned, I remembered my resolution; and, staggering
to my desk, I wrote, in ill-shaped, straggling characters, the all
embracing truth still glimmering in my consciousness. The words were
these (children may smile; the wise will ponder): “<i>A strong smell of
turpentine prevails throughout.</i>”</p>
<p>My digression has served at least to illustrate the radical change which
a slight material cause may produce in our thoughts, and the way we<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_104" id="Page_104">[Pg 104]</SPAN></span>
think about them. If the state just described were prolonged, it would
be called insanity. I have no doubt that there are many ill-organized
perhaps over-organized human brains, to which the common air is what the
vapour of ether was to mine: it is madness to them to drink in this
terrible burning oxygen at every breath; and the atmosphere that enfolds
them is like the flaming shirt of Nessus.</p>
<p>The more we examine the mechanism of thought, the more we shall see that
the automatic, unconscious action of the mind enters largely into all
its processes. Our definite ideas are stepping-stones; how we get from
one to the other, we do not know: something carries us; we do not take
the step. A creating and informing spirit which is with us, and not of
us, is recognized everywhere in real and storied life. It is the Zeus
that kindled the rage of Achilles; it is the muse of Homer; it is the
Daimon of Socrates; it is the inspiration of the seer; it is the mocking
devil that whispers to Margaret as she kneels at the altar; and the
hobgoblin that cried, “Sell him, sell him!” in the ear of John Bunyan:
it shaped the forms that filled the soul of Michael Angelo when he saw
the figure of the great Lawgiver in the yet unhewn marble, and the dome
of the world's yet unbuilt basilica against the black horizon; it comes
to the least of us, as a voice that will be heard; it tells us what we
must believe; it frames our sentences; it lends a sudden gleam of sense
or eloquence to the dullest of us<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_105" id="Page_105">[Pg 105]</SPAN></span> all, so that, like Katterfelto with
his hair on end, we wonder at ourselves, or rather not at ourselves, but
at this divine visitor, who chooses our brain as his dwelling-place, and
invests our naked thought with the purple of the kings of speech or
song.</p>
<p>After all, the mystery of unconscious mental action is exemplified, as I
have said, in every act of mental association. What happens when one
idea brings up another? Some internal movement, of which we are wholly
unconscious and which we only know by its effect. What is this action,
which in Dame Quickly agglutinates contiguous circumstances by their
surfaces; in men of wit and fancy, connects remote ideas by partial
resemblances; in men of imagination, by the vital identity which
underlies phenomenal diversity; in the man of science, groups the
objects of thought in sequences of maximum resemblance? Not one of them
can answer. There is a Delphi and a Pythoness in every human breast. [At
Delphi in ancient Greece was the oracle of Apollo: the Pythoness was his
priestess.]</p>
<p>The poet sits down to his desk with an odd conceit in his brain; and
presently his eyes fill with tears, his thought slides into the minor
key, and his heart is full of sad and plaintive melodies. Or he goes to
his work saying “To-night I would have tears,” and before he rises from
his table he has written a burlesque, such as he might think fit to send
to one of the comic papers, if these were not so commonly cemeteries of
hilarity<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_106" id="Page_106">[Pg 106]</SPAN></span> interspersed with cenotaphs of wit and humour. These strange
hysterics of the intelligence, which make us pass from weeping to
laughter, and from laughter back again to weeping, must be familiar to
every impressible nature; and all is as automatic, involuntary, as
entirely self-evolved by a hidden organic process, as are the changing
moods of the laughing and crying woman. The poet always recognizes a
dictation from without, and we hardly think it a figure of speech when
we talk of his inspiration.</p>
<p>The mental attitude of the poet while writing, if I may venture to
define it, is that of the “nun, breathless with adoration.” Mental
stillness is the first condition of the listening state; and I think my
friends the poets will recognize that the sense of effort, which is
often felt, accompanies the mental spasm by which the mind is maintained
in a state at once passive to the influx from without, and active in
seizing only that which will serve its purpose.<SPAN name="FNanchor_3_3" id="FNanchor_3_3"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_3_3" class="fnanchor">[3]</SPAN> It is not strange
that remembered ideas should often take advantage of the crowd of
thoughts and smuggle themselves in as original. Honest thinkers are
always stealing unconsciously from each other. Our<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_107" id="Page_107">[Pg 107]</SPAN></span> minds are full of
waifs and estrays which we think our own. Innocent plagiarism turns up
everywhere. Our best musical critic tells me that a few notes of the air
of “Shoo Fly” are borrowed from a movement in one of the magnificent
harmonies of Beethoven.</p>
<p>And so the orator—I do not mean the poor slave of a manuscript, who
takes his thought chilled and stiffened from its mould, but the
impassioned speaker who pours it forth as it flows coruscating from the
furnace—the orator only becomes our master at the moment when he
himself is surprised, captured, taken possession of, by a sudden rush of
fresh inspiration. How well we know the flash of the eye, the thrill of
the voice, which are the signature and symbol of nascent
thought—thought just emerging into consciousness, in which condition,
as is the case with the chemist's elements, it has a combining force at
other times wholly unknown!</p>
<p>But we are all more or less improvisators. We all have a double, who is
wiser and better than we are, and who puts thoughts into our heads and
words into our mouths. Do we not all commune with our own hearts upon
our beds? Do we not all divide ourselves and go to<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_108" id="Page_108">[Pg 108]</SPAN></span> buffets on questions
of right or wrong, of wisdom or folly? Who or what is it that resolves
the stately parliament of the day, with all its forms and
conventionalities and pretences, and the great Me presiding, into the
committee of the whole, with Conscience in the chair, that holds its
solemn session through the watches of the night?</p>
<p>Persons who talk most do not always think most. I question whether
persons who think most—that is, have most conscious thought pass
through their minds—necessarily do most mental work. The tree that you
are sticking in “will be growing when you are sleeping.” So with every
new idea that is planted in a real thinker's mind: it will be growing
when he is least conscious of it. An idea in the brain is not a legend
carved on a marble slab: it is an impression made on a living tissue,
which is the seat of active nutritive processes. Shall the initials I
carved in bark increase from year to year with the tree? and shall not
my recorded thought develop into new forms and relations with my growing
brain? Mr. Webster told one of our greatest scholars that he had to
change the size of his hat every few years. His head grew larger as his
intellect expanded. Illustrations of this same fact were shown me many
years ago by Mr. Deville, the famous phrenologist, in London. But
organic mental changes may take place in shorter spaces of time. A
single night of sleep has often brought a sober second-thought,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_109" id="Page_109">[Pg 109]</SPAN></span> which
was a surprise to the hasty conclusion of the day before. Lord
Polkommet's description of the way he prepared himself for a judicial
decision is in point, except for the alcoholic fertilizer he employed in
planting his ideas: “Ye see, I first read a' the pleadings; and then,
after letting them wamble in my wame wi' the toddy two or three days, I
gie my ain interlocutor.”</p>
<p>The problem of memory is closely connected with the question of the
mechanical relation between thought and structure. How intimate is the
alliance of memory with the material condition of the brain, is shown by
the effect of age, of disease, of a blow, of intoxication. I have known
an aged person repeat the same question five, six, or seven times during
the same brief visit. Everybody knows the archbishop's flavour of
apoplexy in the memory as in the other mental powers. I was once asked
to see a woman who had just been injured in the street. On coming to
herself, “Where am I? What has happened?” she asked. “Knocked down by a
horse ma'am; stunned a little: that is all.” A pause, “while one with
moderate haste might count a hundred,” and then again, “Where am I? What
has happened?”—“Knocked down by a horse, ma'am; stunned a little: that
is all.” Another pause, and the same question again; and so on during
the whole time I was by her. The same tendency to repeat a question
indefinitely has been observed in returning members of those
worshipping<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_110" id="Page_110">[Pg 110]</SPAN></span> assemblies whose favourite hymn is “We Won't Go Home Till
Morning.”</p>
<p>Is memory, then, a material record? Is the brain, like the rocks of the
Sinaitic Valley, written all over with inscriptions left by the long
caravans of thought, as they have passed year after year through its
mysterious recesses?</p>
<p>When we see a distant railway-train sliding by us in the same line, day
after day, we infer the existence of a track which guides it. So, when
some dear old friend begins that story we remember so well; switching
off at the accustomed point of digression; coming to a dead stop at the
puzzling question of chronology; off the track on the matter of its
being first or second cousin of somebody's aunt; set on it again by the
patient, listening wife, who knows it all as she knows her well-worn
wedding-ring—how can we doubt that there is a track laid down for the
story in some permanent disposition of the thinking-marrow?</p>
<p>I need not say that no microscope can find the tablet inscribed with the
names of early loves, the stains left by tears of sorrow or contrition,
the rent where the thunderbolt of passion has fallen, or any legible
token that such experiences have formed a part of the life of the
mortal, the vacant temple of whose thought it is exploring. It is only
as an inference, aided by illustration which I will presently offer,
that I suggest the possible existence, in the very substance of the
brain-tissue, of those inscriptions which Shakespeare<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_111" id="Page_111">[Pg 111]</SPAN></span> must have thought
of when he wrote—</p>
<div class="poem"><div class="stanza">
<span class="i2">Pluck from the memory a rooted sorrow;<br/></span>
<span class="i2">Raze out the written troubles of the brain.<br/></span></div>
</div>
<p>The objection to the existence of such a material record—that we renew
our bodies many scores of times and yet retain our earliest
recollections—is entirely met by the fact, that a scar of any kind
holds it own nearly through life in spite of all these same changes, as
we have not far to look to find instances.</p>
<p>It must be remembered that a billion of the starry brain-cells could be
packed in a cubic inch, and that the convolutions contain one hundred
and thirty-four cubic inches, according to the estimate already given.
My illustration is derived from microscopic photography. I have a glass
slide on which there is a minute photographic picture, which is exactly
covered when the head of a small pin is laid upon it. In that little
speck are clearly to be seen, by a proper magnifying power, the
following objects: the Declaration of Independence, with easily
recognized facsimile autographs of all the signers; the arms of all the
original thirteen States; the Capitol at Washington; and very good
portraits of all the Presidents of the United States, from Washington to
Mr. James K. Polk. These objects are all distinguishable as a group with
a power of fifty diameters: with a power of three hundred any one of
them becomes a sizable picture. You may see, if you will, the majesty of
Washington on his noble features, or the will of Jackson in<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_112" id="Page_112">[Pg 112]</SPAN></span> those hard
lines of the long face crowned with that bristling head of hair in a
perpetual state of electrical divergence and centrifugal self-assertion.
Remember that each of these faces is the record of a life.</p>
<p>Now recollect that there was an interval between the exposure of the
negative in the camera and its development by pouring a wash over it,
when all these pictured objects existed potentially, but absolutely
invisible and incapable of recognition, in a speck of collodion-film,
which a pin's head would cover; and then think what Alexandrian
libraries, what Congressional document loads of positively intelligible
characters—such as one look of the recording angel would bring out;
many of which we can ourselves develop at will, or which come before our
eyes unbidden, like “Mene, Mene, Tekel, Upharsin”—might be held in
those convolutions of the brain which wrap the talent entrusted to us,
too often as the folded napkin of the slothful servant hid the treasure
his master had lent him.</p>
<p>Three facts, so familiar that I need only allude to them, show how much
more is recorded in the memory than we may ever take cognizance of. The
first is the conviction of having been in the same precise circumstances
once or many times before. Dr. Wigan says, never but once; but such is
not my experience. The second is the panorama of their past lives, said,
by people rescued from drowning, to have flashed before them. I had it
once myself, accompanied by<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_113" id="Page_113">[Pg 113]</SPAN></span> an ignoble ducking and scrambling
self-rescue. The third is the revival of apparently obsolete
impressions, of which many strange cases are related in nervous young
women and in dying persons, and which the story of the dog Argus in the
“Odyssey,” and of the parrot so charmingly told by Campbell, would lead
us to suppose not of rare occurrence in animals. It is possible,
therefore, and I have tried to show that it is not improbable, that
memory is a material record; that the brain is scarred and seamed with
infinitesimal hieroglyphics, as the features are engraved with the
traces of thought and passion. And, if this is so, must not the record,
we ask, perish with the organ? Alas! how often do we see it perish
<i>before</i> the organ!—the mighty satirist tamed into oblivious
imbecility; the great scholar wandering without sense of time or place
among his alcoves, taking his books one by one from the shelves and
fondly patting them; a child once more among his toys, but a child whose
to-morrows come hungry, and not full-handed—come as birds of prey in
the place of the sweet singers of morning. We must all become as little
children if we live long enough; but how blank an existence the wrinkled
infant must carry into the kingdom of heaven, if the Power that gave him
memory does not repeat the miracle by restoring it!<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_114" id="Page_114"></SPAN></span></p>
<div class="footnotes"><h3>FOOTNOTES:</h3>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_3_3" id="Footnote_3_3"></SPAN><SPAN href="#FNanchor_3_3"><span class="label">[3]</span></SPAN>Burns tell us how he composed verses for a given tune: “My way is, I
consider the poetic sentiment correspondent to my idea of the musical
expression; then choose my theme; begin one stanza. When that is
composed, which is generally the most difficult part of the business, I
walk out, sit down now and then, look out for objects in Nature that are
in unison or harmony with the cogitations of my fancy, and workings of
my bosom; humming every now and then the air with the verses I have
framed. When I feel my Muse beginning to jade I retire to the solitary
fireside of my study, and there commit my effusions to paper; swinging
at intervals on the hind-legs of my elbow-chair, by way of calling forth
my own critical strictures, as my pen goes on.”—“Letters to G.
Thomson,” No. XXXVII.</p>
</div>
</div>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="MEMORY" id="MEMORY"></SPAN>MEMORY</h2>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_115" id="Page_115">[Pg 115]</SPAN></span></p>
<span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></div>
<h3>HENRY MAUDSLEY, M.D.</h3>
<div class="noteb">[Dr. Maudsley, of London, is an eminent physician and psychologist. His
works include “Body and Mind,” “Body and Will,”
“Responsibility in Mental Disease,” “Pathology of the
Mind,” all published by D. Appleton & Co., New York. From the
work last mentioned the following is part of the chapter on Memory and
Imagination.]</div>
<p>No mental development would be possible without memory, for if a man
possessed it not he would be obliged to begin his conscious life afresh
with each impression made upon him, and would be incapable of any
education. We cannot perhaps better define memory than, following Locke,
as the power which the mind has “to revive perceptions which it once had
with this additional perception annexed to them, that it has had them
before;” in other words, as the power or process by which that which has
been once known is, when <i>re</i>presented to the mind, known as a previous
mental experience, that is, is <i>re</i>cognized. When people speak of ideas
being laid up in the memory, they of course speak metaphorically; there
is no such repository in which ideas are stored up, ready to be brought
out when required for use; when an idea which we have once had is
excited again, there is simply a reproduction of the same nervous
current, with<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_116" id="Page_116">[Pg 116]</SPAN></span> the conscious addition that it is a reproduction—it is
the same idea <i>plus</i> the consciousness that it is the same. The question
then suggests itself, What is the physical condition of this
consciousness? What is the modification of the anatomical substrata of
fibres and cells, or of their physiological activity, which is the
occasion of this <i>plus</i> element in the reproduced idea? It may be
supposed that the first activity did leave behind it, when it subsided,
some after-effect, some modification of the nerve element, whereby the
nerve circuit was disposed to fall again readily into the same action;
such disposition appearing in consciousness as <i>re</i>cognition or memory.
Memory is, in fact, the conscious phase of this physiological
disposition when it becomes active or discharges its functions on the
recurrence of the particular mental experience. To assist our conception
of what may happen, let us suppose the individual nerve-elements to be
endowed with their own consciousness, and let us assume them to be, as I
have supposed, modified in a certain way by the first experience; it is
hard to conceive that when they fall into the same action on another
occasion they should not recognize or remember it; for the second action
is a reproduction of the first, with the addition of what it contains
from the after-effects of the first. As we have assumed the process to
be conscious, this reproduction with its addition would be a memory or
remembrance.</p>
<p>Psychology affords us not the least help in this<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_117" id="Page_117">[Pg 117]</SPAN></span> matter, for in
describing memory as a faculty of the mind or the conservative faculty
it does no more than present us with a name in place of our explanation.
But we do get nearer realities when we go down to the organic aptitude
which, in consequence of an action, there is to the recurrence of a
similar action on another occasion. And physiology presents us with many
illustrations of such organized aptitudes. Take, for example, the
education of our movements: a designed movement is performed at first
slowly and clumsily, and it is only by giving great pains to it and
frequently repeating it that we acquire the skill to perform it easily
and quickly; the aptitude thereto being at last so completely organized
in the proper nervous centres that it may be performed without
consciousness on our part, quite automatically. Thus it appears that
memory in this case becomes less conscious as it becomes more complete,
until, when it has reached its greatest perfection and is performed with
the most facility, it is entirely unconscious. After which, if we are
psychologists who are content to rest in words and forbear to pursue the
facts which they denote, we must cease to speak of it as memory: it has
become custom, or habit, or automatism. But if we go beneath words to
the property of the motor nerve-centres whereby they react in a definite
way to impressions made upon them, organically register their
experience, and so acquire by education their special faculties, we
perceive that we have not to do in the higher<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_118" id="Page_118">[Pg 118]</SPAN></span> nerve-centres with
fundamentally different properties of nerve element, but with different
functions which depend upon the same fundamental property. Substitute
the highest nerve-centres for the motor nerve-centres, and the complex
idea for the complex movement, and what has been said of the latter is
strictly true of the former; the idea, like the movement, is accompanied
with less consciousness the more completely it is organized, and when it
has been completely organized it takes its part automatically in our
mental operations, being performed, as a habitual movement is performed,
automatically. The physiological condition of memory is, then, the
organic process by which nerve-experiences in the different centres are
registered; and to recollect is to revive these experiences in the
highest centres, the functions of which are attended with
consciousness—to stimulate, by external or internal causes, their
residua, aptitudes, dispositions, or whatever else we may choose to call
them, into functional activity. Stimulated from without, they constitute
recognition, that is, cognition with memory of former cognition;
stimulated from within, they constitute recollection.</p>
<p>It must be borne in mind, as Dr. Darwin remarked many years ago, that in
dealing with memory we have to do not with laws of light, but with laws
of life, and that the misleading notion of images or ideas of objects
being stored up in the mind has been derived from our experience<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_119" id="Page_119">[Pg 119]</SPAN></span> of the
action of light upon the retina. If we would understand the laws of
organization in the highest nerve-centres, we shall certainly do well to
study organic processes generally; it would be not less absurd to
attempt to understand the higher processes without giving attention to
the lower, than it would be to attempt to build a house without taking
pains to lay its foundations securely. It is a plain matter of
observation that other organic elements besides nervous elements
perpetuate impressions made upon them, which they may accordingly in a
certain sense be said to remember; the virus of smallpox, for example,
makes an impression upon all the elements of the body, which they never
lose, although it becomes fainter with the lapse of time; in some
unknown way it modifies their constitution so that ever afterwards their
susceptibilities are changed. The scar which is left after the healing
of a wound in a child's finger keeps the same relative proportion to the
finger through life, growing as it grows; for the elements of the new
tissue not only renew themselves particle by particle, and thus
perpetuate it, but they extend it in relation with the growth of the
surrounding parts. We need not brave the fire of psychological scorn by
calling this retention of impressions <i>memory</i>, or care greatly what it
is called, so long as due heed is given to the fact; but we may be
permitted to perceive in it the same physiological process which, in the
cortical [outer] layers of the cerebral [brain's]<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_120" id="Page_120">[Pg 120]</SPAN></span> hemispheres, is the
condition of memory, and of habit in thought. Moreover, it may be fairly
demanded of the psychologists that they be consistent, and that they no
longer use the word memory to denote those mental processes which have
been so completely organized that they take place without consciousness;
if it be wrong, as they profess, to assume or imply an unconscious
memory, it must be still more wrong to assume or imply an unconscious
consciousness, as they sometimes do.</p>
<p>In any case, the foregoing considerations cannot fail to show how
misleading it is to look upon perceptions as mere pictures of nature,
and upon the mind as a vast canvas on which they are cunningly painted;
the real process is one of organization, and it is rightly conceivable
only by the aid of ideas derived from the observation of organic
development—namely, the fundamental ideas of Assimilation of the like
and Differentiation of the unlike. Nowhere is it more necessary than in
the study of memory to apprehend clearly that what we call mind is the
function of a mental organization; for thereby we get rid at once of
many empty discussions which have been carried on without definite
result; as, for example, whether memory is a knowledge of the past, or a
knowledge of the present with a belief of the past, and the like.
Moreover, this conception of a mental organization is indispensable to
the explanation of the<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_121" id="Page_121">[Pg 121]</SPAN></span> manifold varieties of partial or general loss of
memory which are produced by injury, disease and decay of brain; for
memory is good or bad according to bodily states, is impaired in various
ways by disease, decays with the decay of structure in old age, and is
extinguished with the extinction of life in the brain.</p>
<p>From of old two kinds of memory have been distinguished, according as
the object remembered occurs to the mind spontaneously, or is
voluntarily sought for; the former being known as <i>memory</i> proper, the
latter as <i>recollection</i>. It is certain that we do recognize this
difference, which common language attests, between that which is revived
without any effort, and that which we endeavour to recover by an effort;
and that men differ much, by virtue of natural capacities, both in
memory and in power of recollection. No doubt much of the difference in
both cases is due to the degree of attention which is given to the
subject when it is first presented to the mind, but this will not
account satisfactorily for all the difference which is observed; some
persons being able to repeat with great ease a row of figures, a number
of dates, or several lines of poetry, after reading them over once,
while others fail to do so with equal success after reading them over
many times. Extraordinary instances have been recorded of this exactness
of memory for details reaching back to the earliest periods of life. I
have seen an imbecile in the Earlswood Asylum for idiots who can repeat<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_122" id="Page_122">[Pg 122]</SPAN></span>
accurately a page or more of any book which he has read years before,
even though it was a book which he did not understand in the least; and
I once saw an epileptic youth, morally imbecile, who would, shutting his
eyes, repeat a leading article in a newspaper word for word, after
reading it once. This kind of memory, in which the person seems to read
a photographic copy of former impressions with his mind's eye, is not
indeed commonly associated with great intellectual power; for what
reason I know not, unless it be that the mind to which it belongs is
prevented by the very excellence of its power of apprehending and
recalling separate facts from rising to that discernment of their higher
relations which is involved in reasoning and judgment, and so stays in a
function which should be the foundation of its further development; or
that, being by some natural defect prevented from rising to the higher
sphere of comprehension of relations, it applies all its energies to the
apprehension of details. Certainly one runs some risk, by overloading
the memory of a child with details, of arresting the development of the
mental powers: stereotyping details on the brain, we prevent that
further development of it which consists in rising from concrete
perception to conception of relations. However, it must be allowed that
there have been a few remarkable instances of extraordinary men who have
combined a wonderful memory for details with the possession of the
highest intellectual powers.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_123" id="Page_123">[Pg 123]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>If we now proceed to examine closely the nature of recollection, it will
be found that the difference between it and simple memory is not
fundamentally so great as appears on the surface. When we voluntarily
try hard to remember something which has been forgotten, and succeed in
the end, the actual revival is done unconsciously and, as it were,
spontaneously; for it is plain that if we were conscious of what we want
we should not need to recollect it, inasmuch as it would already be in
possession; and it is furthermore plain that a definite act of volition
recalling it must imply a consciousness of it, inasmuch as it is
impossible to will what we are not conscious of. Arbitrary recollection
by an act of will is therefore nonsense. What we really do when we try
to recollect is to apply attention to words or ideas which have, in our
past experience, accidental or essential relations to, or associations
with, the forgotten word or idea, voluntarily to keep these ideas active
by making them consciousness and to trust to their power of awakening
into activity that which it is desired to recall; indeed, it is
notorious that the best way of succeeding is, having held the related
ideas energetically in attention for a time, to allow the thoughts to
pass to other things, when the lost idea will, after a longer or shorter
time—sometimes indeed after days—recur to the mind. The actual process
of reproduction is therefore one of simple or spontaneous memory; we
prepare the way for<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_124" id="Page_124">[Pg 124]</SPAN></span> it by stimulating into action the related ideas,
but we positively interfere with its success if, by continuing to keep
them in attention, we do not permit them to do their work spontaneously;
the reason of this being that we thereby hinder the propagation of their
activity to other nerve-circuits. We shall understand this the better if
we realize that consciousness is the <i>result</i> of a certain activity of
idea, not driven to it, but drawn by it, and get rid of the metaphysical
notion that it is some mysterious power which we direct voluntarily to
the idea in order to make it active.</p>
<p>It will not be amiss, before passing from this subject, to take note of
and to ponder that certainty which, in trying to recollect something, we
have of our possession of what we are thus striving to gain consciously,
though we are not conscious what it is. We have the clearest conviction
that, although we have forgotten it, we still have it and may recover
it. How comes it to pass that we are so sure of the existence of that of
which we are not conscious? In the first place, it would appear to
supply an argument in support of the theory that something has been left
behind in the nerve-circuit ministering to the forgotten idea, in other
words, retained by it, which differentiates it from other
nerve-circuits, disposes it to a repetition of its former activity, and
produces the conviction of a latent possession, even when it is not
active, or at any rate not active enough to awaken consciousness.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_125" id="Page_125">[Pg 125]</SPAN></span> In
the second place, it must be remembered that the forgotten idea had
associations with other ideas, which are really part of its meaning; it
may well be, therefore, that when these are active and occupy the
attention, while it remains inactive and below the horizon of
consciousness, there is a tendency or sort of effort to reopen the
former paths of association, in order to their completeness—to make the
circuit, so to speak; and that it is the consciousness of this tendency
or effort which gives rise to the certainty which we have of something
forgotten. Certain it is, that when a stimulus excites one of two
movements which have taken place together or in succession on former
occasions, there is a tendency, when the stimulus is powerful or
continued, to the reproduction of the associated movement; there is a
diffusion of the stimulus along the accustomed path to the associated
motor centres, and a union of movements is the result. A piece of poetry
which has been thoroughly learnt may be repeated mechanically, as a tune
may be whistled, when the proper verbal movements have been once
started; indeed, the repetition in such case is most successful when
consciousness is not too much occupied with it; for it frequently
happens, if we think about the words which we are repeating, we become
uncertain and forget, and are obliged, in order to succeed, to begin
again and allow the succession of movements to go on automatically. We
impede the operation of the spontaneous memory, upon<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_126" id="Page_126">[Pg 126]</SPAN></span> which we really
depend, when, by maintaining the activity of a word in consciousness as
attention, we hinder the propagation thereof to the associated
nerve-circuits.</p>
<p>When a person who is conscious of an idea is striving to revive a
related idea which he has forgotten, he presents an example of memory in
the making; for he is striving to revive the yet incomplete organic
union between them, which was the result of the original apprehension of
their relations, and which, when complete, will cause the one idea to
recall the other instantly and without the least effort, just as a
single sensation of an object at once revives the cluster of sensations
which are combined in the perception of it. The process of intellectual
development consists in the mental organization of related ideas, as
internal representatives of external relations in nature, and in making
this organization so complete that a number of associated ideas shall
act like a single idea, being combined into a complex product and
recalled instantly and without conscious effort, just as a complex
movement is. Then the memory is so complete that we must cease to call
it memory, because it is unconscious. In fact, spontaneous recollection
is at an end when involuntary memory begins, and involuntary memory
merges gradually into a reproduction of former mental experiences which
is as completely automatic as the habitual movements of our daily life.
And well it may be; for the same organic property of<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_127" id="Page_127">[Pg 127]</SPAN></span> nerve
element—indeed, I might say, the same fundamental property of
organization—is at the bottom of both.</p>
<p>Thus much concerning the nature and function of memory. Upon its basis
rests the possibility of mental development, in which there are, as we
have already seen, the organic registration of the <i>simple</i> ideas of the
senses; the assimilation of the like in ideas which takes place in the
production or evolution of <i>general</i> ideas; the assimilation, of the
properties common to two or more general ideas into an <i>abstract</i> idea;
the special organization or differentiation, or discrimination, of
unlike ideas; the organic combination of the ideas derived from the
different senses into one <i>complex</i> idea, with the further manifold
combinations of complex ideas into what Hartley called <i>duplex</i> ideas.
In fact, no limit is assignable to the complexity of combinations which
may go to the formation of a compound idea. Take, for example, the idea
of the universe. But how comes it to pass that a new imaginative
creation of the mind, to which nothing in nature answers, is effected?
By the same process fundamentally as that by which our general and
abstract ideas are formed. For when we consider the matter, it appears
that there are no actual outside existences answering to our most
abstract ideas, which are, therefore, so far new creations of the mind;
in their formation there is a blending or coalescence of the like
relations in two concrete ideas—the development of a<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_128" id="Page_128">[Pg 128]</SPAN></span> <i>concept</i>, there
is, as it were, an extraction of the essential out of the particular, a
sublimation of the concrete; and, by the creation of a new world in
which these essential ideas supersede the concrete ideas, the power of
the mind is most largely extended. Now, although there are no concrete
objects in nature answering to these abstract ideas, yet these are none
the less, when rightly formed, valid and real subjective existences
expressing or signifying the essential relations of things, as the
flower which crowns development expresses the essential nature of the
plant. Thus it is that we rise from the idea of a particular man to the
general idea of man, and from that to the abstract idea of virtue as a
quality of man; so that for the future we can make use of the abstract
idea in all our reasoning, without being compelled to make continual
reference to the concrete. Herein, be it remembered again, we have a
process corresponding with that which ministers to the production of our
motor intuitions; the acquired faculty of certain co-ordinate movements
by means of which complicated acts are automatically performed, and we
are able to do, almost in the twinkling of an eye, what would cost hours
of labour were we compelled on each occasion to go deliberately through
the process of special adaptation, is the equivalent, on the motor side,
of the general idea by which so much time and labour are saved in
reasoning: in both cases there is an internal development in accordance
with fundamental laws, and the organized<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_129" id="Page_129">[Pg 129]</SPAN></span> result is, as every new phase
of development is, a new creation. Creation is not by fits and starts,
but it is continuous in nature.</p>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="COMMON_SENSE" id="COMMON_SENSE"></SPAN>COMMON SENSE</h2>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_131" id="Page_131">[Pg 131]</SPAN></span></p>
<span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></div>
<h3>WILLIAM BOYD CARPENTER, M.D.</h3>
<div class="noteb">[Dr. Carpenter was one of the leading men of science in the generation
which has recently passed away. He was a physician and psychologist of
mark, and withal a geographer of erudition and extensive travel. His
famous work, “Principles of Mental Physiology,” is published
by D. Appleton & Co., New York. Its eleventh chapter, minus a few
paragraphs, is here presented.]</div>
<p>There are two principal forms of common sense which it is desirable
clearly to distinguish. The first is what the philosopher means by
common sense, when he attributes to it the formation of those original
convictions or ultimate beliefs, which cannot be resolved into simpler
elements, and which are accepted by every normally constituted human
being as direct cognitions of his own mental states. It might, indeed,
be maintained that this necessary acceptance of propositions which only
need to be intelligibly stated to command unhesitating and universal
assent, cannot rightly be termed an act of judgment. But just as
sense-perceptions, which are intuitive in the lower animals, have been
acquired in man by a process of self-education in the earliest stages,
in which acts of judgment are continually called for, so may we regard
the autocratic deliverances of the universal common<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_132" id="Page_132">[Pg 132]</SPAN></span> sense of mankind as
really having, in the first instance, the characters of true judgments,
each expressing the general resultant of uniform experience,—which may
be partly of the individual, and partly that of the race embodied in the
constitution of each member of it.</p>
<p>The second or popular acceptance of the term common sense, on the other
hand, is that of an attribute which judges of things whose self-evidence
is not equally apparent to every individual, but presents itself to
different individuals in very different degrees, according in part to
the original constitution of each, and in part to the range of his
experience and degree in which he has profited by it. This is the form
of common sense by which we are mainly guided in the ordinary affairs of
life: but inasmuch as we no longer find its deliverances in uniform
accordance, but encounter continual divergences of judgment as to what
things are self-evident,—some being so to A whilst they are not so to
B, and others being self-evident to B which are not so to A,—it cannot
be trusted as an autocratic or infallible authority. And yet, as Dr.
Reid truly says, “disputes very often terminate in an appeal to common
sense;” this being especially the case, when to doubt its judgment would
be ridiculous.</p>
<p>If the view here taken be correct, these two forms—which may be
designated respectively as elementary and as ordinary common sense—have
fundamentally the same basis; and we may further connect with them as
having a similar<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_133" id="Page_133">[Pg 133]</SPAN></span> genesis, those special forms of common sense, which
are the attributes of such as have applied themselves in a scientific
spirit to any particular course of inquiry,—things coming to be
perfectly self-evident to men of such special culture, which ordinary
men, or men whose special culture has lain in a different direction, do
not apprehend as such.</p>
<p>The judgment of common sense as to any self-evident truth, may be
defined as the immediate or instinctive response that is given (in
psychological language) by the automatic action of the mind, or (in
physiological language) by the reflex-action of the brain to any
question which can be answered by such a direct appeal. The nature and
value of that response will depend upon the acquired condition of the
mind, or of the brain, at the time it is given; that condition being the
general resultant of the whole psychical activity of the individual. The
particular form of that activity is determined, as we have seen, in the
first place, by his original constitution; secondly, by the influences
which have been early brought to bear upon it from without; and thirdly,
by his own power of self-direction. And it may be said that while the
elementary form of common sense depends mainly upon the first of these
factors, its ordinary form chiefly arises out of the first and second,
and its special forms almost exclusively out of the third;—the response
being given, in each case, by a nervous mechanism, in the organization
of which the generalized results<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_134" id="Page_134">[Pg 134]</SPAN></span> of the past experiences of
consciousness (whether of the race or of the individual) have become
embodied.</p>
<p>The parallel between the cerebral action which furnishes the mechanism
of thought now under consideration, and the action of the sensori-motor
apparatus which furnishes the mechanism of sense and motion, is
extremely close. We have seen that there are certain sense-perceptions,
which, although not absolutely intuitive, very early come to possess—in
every normally constituted human being—the immediateness and perfection
of those corresponding perceptions which are intuitive in the lower
animals; and that with these are associated certain respondent motions,
which, though acquired by practice in the first instance, ultimately
come to be performed as by a second nature. Certain of these motions,
such as walking erect, are universally acquired; and thus obviously come
to be the expressions of the original endowments of the mechanism,
trained by an experience very similar in the uniformity of its character
to that which educates the elementary form of common sense. For it must
be clear to any one who compares the erect progression of a child who
has just learned to walk, with that of a dancing dog or even of a
chimpanzee, that while experience makes its acquirement possible in each
case, only an organism which is at the same time structurally adapted
for erect progression and possessed of a special co-ordinating faculty,
can<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_135" id="Page_135">[Pg 135]</SPAN></span> turn such experience to full account. The balancing the body in the
erect position at starting, the maintenance of that balance by a new
adjustment of the centre of gravity as the base of support is shifted
from side to side and from behind forwards, and the alternate lifting
and advance of the legs, involve the harmonious co-operation of almost
all the muscles in the body. Although this co-operation is brought about
in the first instance by the purposive direction of our efforts towards
a given end, under the guidance of our visual and muscular sensations,
yet when we have once learned to walk erect, we find ourselves able to
maintain our balance without any exertion of which we are conscious; all
that is necessary for the performance of this movement being that a
certain stimulus (volitional, or some other) shall call the mechanism
into activity.—But further, we have seen that special powers of
sense-perception can be acquired by the habitual direction of the
attention to particular classes of objects; and that special movements
come to be the secondarily automatic expression of them. How nearly
related these are to the preceding, we may assure ourselves by attending
to the process by which an adult learns to walk on a narrow base, such
as a rope or the edge of a plank. For the co-ordinating action has here
to be gone through afresh under altered and more special conditions, so
as to give a greater development to the balancing power; yet when this
has been fully acquired,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_136" id="Page_136">[Pg 136]</SPAN></span> it is exerted automatically with such an
immediateness and perfection, that a Blondin can cross Niagara on his
rope with no more danger of falling into the torrent beneath, than any
ordinary man would experience if walking without side-rails along the
broad platform of the suspension bridge which spans it. Now since in
those cases in which man acquires powers that are original or intuitive
in the lower animals, there is the strongest reason for believing that a
mechanism forms itself in him which is equivalent to that congenitally
possessed by them, we seem fully justified in the belief that in those
more special forms of activity which are the result of prolonged
training, the sensori-motor apparatus grows to the mode in which it is
habitually exercised, so as to become fit for the immediate execution of
the mandate it receives: it being often found to act not only without
intelligent direction, but without any consciousness of exertion, in
immediate response to some particular kind of stimulus,—just as an
automaton that executes one motion when a certain spring is touched,
will execute a very different one when set going in some other way.</p>
<p>There is strong analogical ground, then, for the belief that the higher
part of the nervous mechanism which is concerned in psychical action,
will follow the same law; embodying the generalized result of its
experiences, so as to become able to evolve, by a direct response, a
result of which the attainment originally required the intervention<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_137" id="Page_137">[Pg 137]</SPAN></span> of
the conscious mind at several intermediate stages of the process. What
there is strong ground for believing in regard to the perceptional
consciousness, may fairly be extended to the ideational, which is so
intimately connected to it, the unconscious co-ordinating action, which
in the former case brings the whole experience to bear upon the
question, whilst the decisions of the latter are based upon a limited,
and therefore one-sided, view of it,—the defect of judgment being due
either to an original want of the co-ordinating power, or to disuse of
the exercise of it through the limitation of the attention to special
fields of study. It may often be noticed that children display a power
of bringing common sense to bear upon the ordinary affairs of life,
which seems much beyond that of their elders; and yet a very sensible
child will often grow into a much less sensible man. Now the reason of
this seems to be, that the child perceives the application of
self-evident considerations to the case at issue, without being
embarrassed by a number of other considerations (perhaps of a trivial or
conventional nature) which distract the attention and unduly influence
the judgment of the adult. And the deliverances of a child's common
sense thus often resemble those of the old court fools, or jesters,
whose function seems to have been to speak out home truths which timid
courtiers would not venture to utter. Moreover, as has been well
remarked, “it is quite possible for minds of limited power to<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_138" id="Page_138">[Pg 138]</SPAN></span> manage a
small range of experience much better than a large, to get confused (as
it were) with resources on too great a scale, and therefore to show far
more common sense within the comparatively limited field of childish
experience, than in the greater world of society or public life. This is
probably the explanation of a thing often seen,—how very sagacious
people instinctively shrink from a field which their tact tells them is
too large for them to manage, and keep to one where they are really
supreme.”</p>
<p>Now, in so far as our conscious mental activity is under the direction
of our will, we can improve this form of common sense, as to both its
range and the trustworthiness of its judgments, by appropriate training.
Such training, as regards the purely intellectual aspect of common
sense, will consist in the determinate culture of the habit of honestly
seeking for truth,—dismissing prejudice, setting aside self-interest,
searching out all that can be urged on each side of the question at
issue, endeavouring to assign to every fact and argument its real value,
and then weighing the two aggregates against each other with judicial
impartiality. For in proportion to the steadiness with which this course
is volitionally pursued, must be its effectiveness in shaping the
mechanism whose automatic action constitutes the unconscious thinking,
of which the results express themselves in our common-sense judgments.</p>
<p>The ordinary common sense of mankind, disciplined<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_139" id="Page_139">[Pg 139]</SPAN></span> and enlarged by an
appropriate culture, becomes one of the most valuable instruments of
scientific inquiry; affording in many instances the best and sometimes
the only basis for a rational conclusion. A typical case, in which no
special knowledge is required, is afforded by the flint implements of
the Abbeville and Amiens gravel beds. No logical proof can be adduced
that the peculiar shapes of these flints were given to them by human
hands; but no unprejudiced person who has examined them now doubts it.</p>
<p>The evidence of design to which, after an examination of one or two such
specimens, we should only be justified in attaching a probable value,
derives an irresistible cogency from accumulation. On the other hand,
the improbability that these flints acquired their peculiar shape by
accident, becomes to our minds greater and greater as more and more such
specimens are found; until at last this hypothesis, although it cannot
be directly disproved, is felt to be almost inconceivable, except by
minds previously possessed by the dominant idea of the modern origin of
man. And thus what was in the first instance a matter of discussion, has
now become one of those self-evident propositions, which claim the
unhesitating assent of all whose opinion on the subject is entitled to
the least weight.</p>
<p>We proceed upwards, however, from such questions as the common sense of
mankind<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_140" id="Page_140">[Pg 140]</SPAN></span> generally is competent to decide, to those in which special
knowledge is required to give value to the judgment; and here we must
distinguish between those departments of inquiry in which scientific
conclusions are arrived at by a process of strict reasoning, and those
in which they partake of the nature of common sense judgments.</p>
<p>Of the former class we have a typical example in mathematics, and in
those exact sciences which make use of mathematics as their instrument
of proof; but even in these, it is common sense which affords not only
the basis, but the materials of the fabric. For while the axioms of
geometry are self-evident truths which not only do not require proof,
but are not capable of being proved in all their universality, every
step of a demonstration is an assertion of which our acceptance depends
on our incapability of conceiving either the contrary or anything else
than the thing asserted. And thus the certain assurance of the proof
felt by every person capable of understanding a mathematical
demonstration, depends upon the conclusive self-evidence of each step of
it. But we not unfrequently meet with individuals, not deficient in
ordinary common sense, who cannot be brought to see this self-evidence;
whilst, on the other hand, the advanced mathematician, when adventuring
into new paths of inquiry, is able to take a great deal for granted as
self-evident, which at an earlier stage of his researches would<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_141" id="Page_141">[Pg 141]</SPAN></span> not
have so presented itself to his mind. The deliverances of this acquired
intuition can in most cases be readily justified by the reasoning
process which they have anticipated. But the genius of a
mathematician—that is, his special aptitude developed by special
culture—will occasionally enable him to divine a truth, of which,
though he may be able to prove it experientially, neither he nor any
other can at the time furnish a logical demonstration. In this divining
power we have clear evidence of the existence of a capacity which cannot
be accounted for by the mere co-ordination of antecedent experiences,
whether of the individual or of the race; and yet, as already shown,
such co-ordination has furnished the stimulus to its development.</p>
<p>Of those departments of science, on the other hand, in which our
conclusions rest (like those of ordinary common sense) not on any one
set of experiences, but upon our unconscious co-ordination of the whole
aggregate of our experiences,—not on the conclusiveness of any one
train of reasoning, but on the convergence of all our lines of thought
towards one centre,—geology may be taken as a typical example. For this
inquiry brings (as it were) into one focus, the light afforded by a
great variety of studies,—physical and chemical, geographical and
biological; and throws it on the pages of that great stone book in which
the past history of our globe is recorded. And its real progress dates
from<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_142" id="Page_142">[Pg 142]</SPAN></span> the time when that common sense method of interpretation came to
be generally adopted, which consists in seeking the explanation of past
changes in the forces at present in operation, instead of invoking (as
the older geologists were wont to do) the aid of extraordinary and
mysterious agencies.</p>
<p>Of the adequacy of common sense to arrive at a decisive judgment under
the guidance of the convergence just indicated, we have a good example
in the following occurrence:—A man having had his pocket picked of a
purse, and the suspected thief having been taken with a purse upon him,
the loser was asked if he could swear to it as his property. This he
could not do; but as he was able to name not only the precise sum which
the purse contained, but also the pieces of money of which that sum
consisted, the jury unhesitatingly assigned to him the ownership of the
purse and its contents. A mathematician could have calculated, from the
number of coins, what were the chances against the correctness of a mere
guess; but no such calculation could have added to the assurance
afforded by common sense, that the man who could tell not only the
number of coins in the purse, but the value of each one of them, must
have been its possessor.</p>
<p>Familiar instances of the like formation of a basis of judgment by the
unconscious co-ordination of experiences, will be found in many
occurrences of daily life; in which the effect of special training
manifests itself in the formation of<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_143" id="Page_143">[Pg 143]</SPAN></span> decisions, that are not the less
to be trusted because they do not rest on assignable reasons:—Thus, a
literary man, who has acquired by culture the art of writing correctly
and forcibly, without having ever formally studied either grammar, the
logical analysis of sentences, or the artifices of rhetoric, will
continually feel in criticizing his own writings or those of others,
that there is something faulty in style or construction, and may be able
to furnish the required correction, whilst altogether unable to say in
what the passage is wrong, or why his amendment sets it right. Or, to
pass into an entirely different sphere, a practised detective will often
arrive, by a sort of divination, at a conviction of the guilt or
innocence of a suspected person, which ultimately turns out to be
correct; and yet he could not convey to another any adequate reasons for
his assurance, which depends upon the impression made upon his mind by
minute details of look, tone, gesture, or manner, which have little or
no significance to ordinary observers, but which his specially cultured
common sense instinctively apprehends.</p>
<p>But in the ordinary affairs of life, our common sense judgments are so
largely influenced by the emotional part of our nature—our individual
likes and dislikes, the predominance of our selfish or of our benevolent
affections, and so on,—that their value will still more essentially
depend upon the earnestness and persistency of our<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_144" id="Page_144">[Pg 144]</SPAN></span> self-direction
towards the right.<SPAN name="FNanchor_4_4" id="FNanchor_4_4"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_4_4" class="fnanchor">[4]</SPAN> The more faithfully, strictly, and perseveringly
we try to disentangle ourselves from all selfish aims, all conscious
prejudices, the more shall we find ourselves progressively emancipated
from those unconscious prejudices, which cling around us as results of
early misdirection and habits of thought and which (having become
embodied in our organization) are more dangerous than those against
which we knowingly put ourselves on guard. And so, in proportion to the
degree in which we habituate ourselves to try every question by first
principles, rather than by the supposed dictates of a temporary
expediency, will the mechanism of our unconscious thinking form itself
in accordance with those principles, so often as to evolve results which
satisfy both ourselves and others with their self-evident truthfulness
and rectitude. It has been well remarked<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_145" id="Page_145">[Pg 145]</SPAN></span> by a man of large experience
of human nature and action, that the habitual determination to do the
right thing, marvellously clears the judgment as to matters purely
intellectual or prudential, having in themselves no moral bearing.</p>
<p>Of this we have a good illustration in the advice which an eminent and
experienced judge (the story is told of Lord Mansfield) is said to have
given to a younger friend, newly appointed to a colonial
judgeship:—“Never give reasons for your decisions; your judgments will
very probably be right, but your reasons will almost certainly be
wrong.” The meaning of this may be taken to be:—“Your legal instinct,
or specially trained common sense, based on your general knowledge of
law, guided by your honesty of intention, will very probably lead you to
correct conclusions; but your knowledge of the technicalities of law is
not sufficient to enable you to give reasons for these conclusions,
which shall bear the test of hostile scrutiny.”</p>
<p>But further, in any of those complicated questions that are pretty sure
to come before us all at some time or other in our lives,—as to which
there is a great deal to be said on both sides; in which it is difficult
to say what is prudent and even what is right; in which it is not duty
and inclination that are at issue, but one set of duties and
inclinations at issue with another,—experience justifies the conclusion
to which science seems to point, that the habitually well-regulated mind
forms its surest judgment by trusting to<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_146" id="Page_146">[Pg 146]</SPAN></span> the automatic guidance of its
common sense; just as a rider who has lost his road is more likely to
find his way home by dropping the reins on his horse's neck, than by
continuing to jerk them to this side or that in the vain search for it.
For continued argument and discussion, in which the feelings are excited
on one side, provoke antagonistic feelings on the other; and no true
balance can be struck until all these adventitious influences have
ceased to operate. When all the considerations which ought to be taken
into the account have been once brought fully before the mind, it is far
better to leave them to arrange themselves, by turning the conscious
activity of the mind into some other direction, or by giving it a
complete repose. If adequate time be given for this unconscious
co-ordination, which is especially necessary when the feelings have been
strongly and deeply moved, we find, when we bring the question again
under consideration, that the direction in which the mind gravitates is
a safer guide than any judgment formed when we are fresh from its
discussion.</p>
<p>Not only may the range and value of such common sense judgments be
increased by appropriate culture in the individual, for, of all parts of
our higher nature, the aptitude for forming them is probably that which
is most capable of being transmitted hereditarily; so that the
descendant of a well-educated ancestry constitutionally possesses in it
much higher<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_147" id="Page_147">[Pg 147]</SPAN></span> measure than the progeny of any savage race. And it seems
to be in virtue of this automatic co-ordination of the elements of
judgment, rather than of any process of conscious ratiocination, that
the race, like the individual, emancipates itself from early prejudices,
gets rid of worn-out beliefs, and learns to look at things as they are,
rather than as they have been traditionally represented. This is what is
really expressed by the progress of rationalism. For although that
progress undoubtedly depends in great part upon the more general
diffusion of knowledge and the higher culture of those intellectual
powers which are exercised in the acquirement of it, yet this alone
would be of little avail, if the self-discipline thus exerted did not
act downwards in improving the mechanism that evolves the self-evident
material of our reasoning processes, as well as upwards in more highly
elaborating their product. If we examine, for instance, the history of
the decline of the belief in witchcraft, we find that it was not killed
by discussion, but perished of neglect. The common sense of the best
part of mankind has come to be ashamed of ever having put any faith in
things whose absurdity now appears self-evident; no discussion of
evidence once regarded as convincing is any longer needed; and it is
only among those of our hereditarily uneducated population, whose
general intelligence is about on a par with that of a Hottentot or an
Esquimaux, that we any longer find such faith entertained.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_148" id="Page_148">[Pg 148]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>There is, in fact, a sort of under-current, not of actually formed
opinion, but of tendency to the formation of opinions, in certain
directions, which bursts every now and then to the surface; exhibiting a
latent preparedness in the public mind to look at great questions in a
new point of view, which leads to most striking results when adequately
guided. That “the hour is come—and the man” is what history
continually reproduces; neither can do anything effectively without the
other. But a great idea thrown out by a mind in advance of its age,
takes root and germinates in secret, shapes the unconscious thought of a
few individuals of the next generation, is by them diffused still more
widely, and thus silently matures itself in the womb of time, until it
comes forth, like Minerva, in full panoply of power.</p>
<p>Those who are able to look back with intelligent retrospect over the
political history of the last half-century and who witness the now
general pervasion of the public mind by truths which it accepts as
self-evident, and by moral principles which it regards as beyond
dispute, can scarcely realize to themselves the fact that within their
own recollection the fearless assertors of those truths and principles
were scoffed at as visionaries or reviled as destructives. And those
whose experience is limited to a more recent period, must see, in the
rapid development of public opinion on subjects of the highest
importance, the evidence of a previous unconscious<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_149" id="Page_149">[Pg 149]</SPAN></span> preparedness, which
may be believed to consist mainly in the higher development and more
general diffusion of that automatic co-ordinating power, which
constitutes the essence of reason as distinct from reasoning.</p>
<p>Thus, then, every course of intellectual and moral self-discipline,
steadily and honestly pursued, tends not merely to clear the mental
vision of the individual, but to ennoble the race; by helping to develop
that intuitive power, which arises in the first instance from the
embodiment in the human constitution of the general resultants of
antecedent experience, but which, in its highest form, far transcends
the experience that has furnished the materials for its evolution,—just
as the creative power of imagination shapes out conceptions which no
merely constructive skill could devise.</p>
<div class="footnotes"><h3>FOOTNOTES:</h3>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_4_4" id="Footnote_4_4"></SPAN><SPAN href="#FNanchor_4_4" class="label">[4]</SPAN> Note by Editor. Sir Henry Taylor in “The Statesman” says:—</p>
<p>“If there be in the character not only sense and soundness, but virtue
of a high order, then, however little appearance there may be of talent,
a certain portion of wisdom may be relied upon almost implicitly. For
the correspondencies of wisdom and goodness are manifold; and that they
will accompany each other is to be inferred, not only because men's
wisdom makes them good, but also because their goodness makes them wise.
Questions of right and wrong are a perpetual exercise of the faculties
of those who are solicitous as to the right and wrong of what they do
and see; and a deep interest of the heart in these questions carries
with it a deeper cultivation of the understanding than can be easily
effected by any other excitement to intellectual activity.”</p>
</div>
</div>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="A_LIBERAL_EDUCATION" id="A_LIBERAL_EDUCATION"></SPAN>A LIBERAL EDUCATION</h2>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_151" id="Page_151">[Pg 151]</SPAN></span></p>
<span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></div>
<h3>PROFESSOR T. H. HUXLEY</h3>
<div class="noteb"> [In 1868 Professor Huxley delivered an address to the South London
Workingmen's College, part of which follows. The address appears in full
in the third volume of the author's essays, published by D. Appleton
& Co., New York.] </div>
<p>What is education? Above all things, what is our ideal of a thoroughly
liberal education?—of that education which, if we could begin life
again, we would give ourselves—of that education which, if we could
mould the fates to our own will, we would give our children? Well, I
know not what may be your conceptions upon this matter, but I will tell
you mine, and I hope I shall find that our views are not very
discrepant.</p>
<p>Suppose it were perfectly certain that the life and fortune of every one
of us would, one day or other, depend upon his losing or winning a game
of chess. Don't you think that we should all consider it to be a primary
duty to learn at least the names and moves of the pieces; to have a
notion of a gambit, and a keen eye for all the means of giving and
getting out of check? Do you not think that we should look with a
disapprobation amounting to scorn, upon the father who allowed his son,
or the State which allowed<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_152" id="Page_152">[Pg 152]</SPAN></span> its members, to grow up without knowing a
pawn from a knight?</p>
<p>Yet it is a very plain and elementary truth, that the life, the fortune,
and the happiness of every one of us, and, more or less, of those who
are connected with us, do depend upon our knowing something of the rules
of a game infinitely more difficult and complicated than chess? It is a
game which has been played for untold ages, every man and woman of us
being one of the two players in a game of his or her own. The
chess-board is the world, the pieces are the phenomena of the universe,
the rules of the game are what we call the laws of Nature. The player on
the other side is hidden from us. We know that his play is always fair,
just and patient. But also we know, to our cost, that he never overlooks
a mistake, or makes the smallest allowance for ignorance. To the man who
plays well, the highest stakes are paid, with that sort of overflowing
generosity with which the strong shows delight in strength. And one who
plays ill is checkmated—without haste, but without remorse.</p>
<p>My metaphor will remind some of you of the famous picture in which
Retzsch has depicted Satan playing at chess with man for his soul.
Substitute for the mocking fiend in that picture a calm, strong angel
who is playing for love, as we say, and would rather lose than win—and
I should accept it as an image of human life.</p>
<p>Well, what I mean by Education is learning the rules of this mighty
game. In other words,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_153" id="Page_153">[Pg 153]</SPAN></span> education is the instruction of the intellect in
the laws of Nature, under which name I include not merely things and
their forces, but men and their ways; and the fashioning of the
affections and of the will into an earnest and loving desire to move in
harmony with those laws. For me, education means neither more nor less
than this. Anything which professes to call itself education must be
tried by this standard, and if it fails to stand the test, I will not
call it education, whatever may be the force of authority, or of
numbers, upon the other side.</p>
<p>It is important to remember that, in strictness, there is no such thing
as an uneducated man. Take an extreme case. Suppose that an adult man,
in the full vigour of his faculties, could be suddenly placed in the
world, as Adam is said to have been, and then left to do as he best
might. How long would he be left uneducated? Not five minutes. Nature
would begin to teach him, through the eye, the ear, the touch, the
properties of objects. Pain and pleasure would be at his elbow telling
him to do this and avoid that; and by slow degrees the man would receive
an education which, if narrow, would be thorough, real, and adequate to
his circumstances, though there would be no extras and very few
accomplishments.</p>
<p>And if to this solitary man entered a second Adam, or, better still, an
Eve, a new and greater world, that of social and moral phenomena, would
be revealed. Joys and woes, compared with<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_154" id="Page_154">[Pg 154]</SPAN></span> which all others would seem
but faint shadows, would spring from the new relations. Happiness and
sorrow would take the place of the coarser monitors, pleasure and pain;
but conduct would still be shaped by the observation of the natural
consequences of actions; or, in other words, by the laws of the nature
of man.</p>
<p>To every one of us the world was once as fresh and new as to Adam. And
then, long before we were susceptible of any other modes of instruction,
Nature took us in hand, and every minute of waking life brought its
educational influence, shaping our actions into rough accordance with
Nature's laws, so that we might not be ended untimely by too gross
disobedience. Nor should I speak of this process of education as past
for any one, be he as old as he may. For every man the world is as fresh
as it was at the first day, and as full of untold novelties for him who
has the eyes to see them. And Nature is still continuing her patient
education of us in that great university, the universe, of which we are
all members.</p>
<p>Those who take honours in Nature's university, who learn the laws which
govern men and things and obey them, are the really great and successful
men in this world. The great mass of mankind are the “Poll,” who pick up
just enough to get through without much discredit. Those who won't learn
at all are plucked; and then you can't come up again. Nature's pluck
means extermination.</p>
<p>Thus the question of compulsory education is<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_155" id="Page_155">[Pg 155]</SPAN></span> settled so far as Nature
is concerned. Her bill on that question was framed and passed long ago.
But, like all compulsory legislation, that of Nature is harsh and
wasteful in its operation. Ignorance is visited as sharply as wilful
disobedience—incapacity meets with the same punishment as crime.
Nature's discipline is not even a word and a blow, and the blow first;
but the blow without the word. It is left to you to find out why your
ears are boxed.</p>
<p>The object of what we commonly call education—that education in which
man intervenes and which I shall distinguish as artificial education—is
to make good these defects in Nature's methods; to prepare the child to
receive Nature's education, neither incapably nor ignorantly, nor with
wilful disobedience; and to understand the preliminary symptoms of her
pleasure, without waiting for the box on the ear. In short, all
artificial education ought to be an anticipation of natural education.
And a liberal education is an artificial education which has not only
prepared a man to escape the great evils of disobedience to natural
laws, but has trained him to appreciate and to seize upon the rewards,
which Nature scatters with as free a hand as her penalties.</p>
<p>That man, I think, has had a liberal education who has been so trained
in youth that his body is the ready servant of his will, and does with
ease and pleasure all the work that, as a mechanism, it is capable of;
whose intellect is a clear, cold,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_156" id="Page_156">[Pg 156]</SPAN></span> logic engine, with all its parts of
equal strength, and in smooth working order; ready, like a steam engine,
to be turned to any kind of work and spin the gossamers as well as forge
the anchors of the mind; whose mind is stored with a knowledge of the
great and fundamental truths of Nature and of the laws of her
operations; one who, no stunted ascetic, is full of life and fire, but
whose passions are trained to come to heel by a vigorous will, the
servant of a tender conscience; who has learned to love all beauty,
whether of Nature or of art, to hate all vileness, and to respect others
as himself.</p>
<p>Such an one and no other, I conceive, has had a liberal education; for
he is, as completely as a man can be, in harmony with Nature. He will
make the best of her, and she of him. They will get on together rarely;
she as his ever beneficent mother; he as her mouthpiece, her conscious
self, her minister and interpreter.</p>
<p>[Then follows an account of English primary schools in 1868, setting
forth defects many of which have since been removed.]</p>
<p>Least of all, does the child gather from this primary “education” of
ours a conception of the laws of the physical world, or of the relations
of cause and effect therein. And this is the more to be lamented, as the
poor are especially exposed to physical evils, and are more interested
in removing them than any other class of the community. If any one is
concerned in knowing the ordinary laws of mechanics one would think<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_157" id="Page_157">[Pg 157]</SPAN></span> it
is the hand-labourer, whose daily toil lies among levers and pulleys; or
among the other implements of artisan work. And if any one is interested
in the laws of health, it is the poor workman, whose strength is wasted
by ill-prepared food, whose strength is sapped by bad ventilation and
bad drainage, and half whose children are massacred by disorders which
might be prevented. Not only does our present primary education
carefully abstain from hinting to the workman that some of his greatest
evils are traceable to mere physical agencies, which could be removed by
energy, patience, and frugality; but it does worse—it renders him, so
far as it can, deaf to those who could help him, and tries to substitute
an Oriental submission to what is falsely declared to be the will of
God, for his natural tendency to strive after a better condition.</p>
<p>What wonder, then, if very recently an appeal has been made to
statistics for the profoundly foolish purpose of showing that education
is of no good—that it diminishes neither misery nor crime among the
masses of mankind? I reply, why should the thing which is called
education do either the one or the other? If I am a knave or a fool,
teaching me to read or write won't make me less of either one or the
other—unless somebody shows me how to put my reading and writing to
wise and good purposes.</p>
<p>Suppose any one were to argue that medicine is of no use, because it
could be proven statistically,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_158" id="Page_158">[Pg 158]</SPAN></span> that the percentage of deaths was just
the same among people who had been taught how to open a medicine chest,
and among those who did not so much as know the key by sight. The
argument is absurd; but it is not more preposterous than that against
which I am contending. The only medicine for suffering, crime, and all
the other woes of mankind, is wisdom. Teach a man to read and write, and
you have put into his hands the great keys of the wisdom box. But it is
quite another matter whether he ever opens the box or not. And he is as
likely to poison as to cure himself, if, without guidance, he swallows
the first drug that comes to hand. In these times a man may as well be
purblind, as unable to read—lame, as unable to write. But I protest
that, if I thought the alternative were a necessary one, I would rather
that the children of the poor should grow up ignorant of both these
mighty arts than that they should remain ignorant of that knowledge to
which these arts are means.</p>
<p>It may be said that all these animadversions may apply to primary
schools, but that the higher schools, at any rate, must be allowed to
give a liberal education. In fact they professedly sacrifice everything
else to this object.</p>
<p>Let us inquire into this matter. What do the higher schools, those to
which the great middle-class of the country sends its children, teach,
over and above the instruction given in the primary schools? There is a
little more reading and writing of English. But, for all that, every<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_159" id="Page_159">[Pg 159]</SPAN></span>
one knows that it is a rare thing to find a boy of the middle or upper
classes who can read aloud decently, or who can put his thoughts on
paper in clear and grammatical (to say nothing of good or elegant)
language. The “ciphering” of the lower schools expands into elementary
mathematics in the higher; into arithmetic, with a little algebra, a
little Euclid. But I doubt if one boy in five hundred has ever heard the
explanation of a rule of arithmetic, or knows his Euclid otherwise than
by rote.</p>
<p>Of theology, the middle-class schoolboy gets rather less than poorer
children, less absolutely and less relatively, because there are so many
other claims upon his attention. I venture to say that, in the great
majority of cases, his ideas on this subject when he leaves school are
of the most shadowy and vague description, and associated with painful
impressions of the weary hours spent in learning collects and catechism
by heart.</p>
<p>Modern geography, modern history, modern literature; the English
language as a language; the whole circle of the sciences, physical,
moral, and social, are even more completely ignored in the higher than
in the lower schools. Up till within a few years back a boy might have
passed through any one of the great public schools with the greatest
distinction and credit, and might never so much as have heard of the
subjects I have just mentioned. He might never have heard that the earth
goes round the sun; that<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_160" id="Page_160">[Pg 160]</SPAN></span> England underwent a great revolution in 1688,
and France another in 1789; that there once lived certain notable men
called Chaucer, Shakespeare, Milton, Voltaire, Goethe, Schiller. The
first might be a German and the last an Englishman for anything he could
tell you to the contrary. And as for science, the only idea the word
would suggest to his mind would be dexterity in boxing.</p>
<p>I have said that this was the state of things a few years back, for the
sake of the few righteous who are to be found among the educational
cities of the plain. But I would not have you too sanguine about the
result, if you sound the minds of the existing generation of public
schoolboys, on such topics as those I have mentioned.</p>
<p>Now let us pause to consider this wonderful state of affairs; for the
time will come when Englishmen will quote it as the stock example of the
stolid stupidity of their ancestors in the nineteenth century. The most
thoroughly commercial people, the greatest voluntary wanderers and
colonists the world has ever seen, are precisely the middle class of
this country. If there be a people which has been busy making history on
the great scale for the last three hundred years—and the most
profoundly interesting history—history which, if it happened to be that
of Greece or Rome, we should study with avidity—it is the English. If
there be a people which, during the same period, has developed a
remarkable literature, it is our own.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_161" id="Page_161">[Pg 161]</SPAN></span> If there be a nation whose
prosperity depends absolutely and wholly upon their mastery over the
forces of Nature, upon their intelligent apprehension of and obedience
to the laws of the creation and distribution of wealth, and of the
stable equilibrium of the forces of society, it is precisely this
nation. And yet this is what these wonderful people tell their
sons:—“At the cost of from one to two thousand pounds of our
hard-earned money, we devote twelve of the most precious years of your
lives to school. There you shall toil, or be supposed to toil; but there
you shall not learn one single thing of all those you will most want to
know directly you leave school and enter upon the practical business of
life. You will in all probability go into business, but you shall not
know where, or how, any article of commerce is produced, or the
difference between an export or an import, or the meaning of the word
'capital.' You will very likely settle in a colony, but you shall not
know whether Tasmania is part of New South Wales or <i>vice versa</i>.</p>
<p>“Very probably you may become a manufacturer, but you shall not be
provided with the means of understanding the working of one of your own
steam engines, or of the nature of the raw products you employ; and,
when you are asked to buy a patent, you shall not have the slightest
means of judging whether the inventor is an impostor who is contravening
the elementary principles of science, or a man who will make you as rich
as Crœsus.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_162" id="Page_162">[Pg 162]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>“You will very likely get into the House of Commons. You will have to
take your share in making laws which may prove a blessing or a curse to
millions of men. But you shall not hear one word respecting the
political organization of your country; the meaning of the controversy
between free-traders and protectionists shall never have been mentioned
to you; you shall not so much as know that there are any such things as
economical laws.</p>
<p>“The mental power which will be of most importance in your daily life
will be the power of seeing things as they are without regard to
authority; and of drawing accurate general conclusions from particular
facts. But at school and at college you shall know of no source of truth
but authority; nor exercise your reasoning faculty upon anything but
deduction from what is laid down by authority.</p>
<p>“You will have to weary your soul with work, and many a time eat your
bread in sorrow and in bitterness, and you shall not have learned to
take refuge in the great source of pleasure without alloy, the serene
resting-place for worn human nature,—the world of art.”</p>
<p>Said I not rightly that we are a wonderful people? I am quite prepared
to allow that education entirely devoted to these omitted subjects might
not be a completely liberal education. But is an education which ignores
them all a liberal education? Nay, is it too much to say that the
education which should embrace<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_163" id="Page_163">[Pg 163]</SPAN></span> these subjects and no others would be a
real education, though an incomplete one; while an education which omits
them is really not an education at all, but a more or less useful course
of intellectual gymnastics?</p>
<p>For what does the middle-class school put in the place of all these
things which are left out? It substitutes what is usually comprised
under the compendious title of the “classics”—that is to say, the
languages, the literature and the history of the ancient Greeks and
Romans, and the geography of so much of the world as was known to these
two great nations of antiquity. Now, do not expect me to depreciate the
earnest and enlightened pursuit of classical learning. I have not the
least desire to speak ill of such occupations, nor any sympathy with
them who run them down. On the contrary, if my opportunities had lain in
that direction, there is no investigation into which I could have thrown
myself with greater delight than that of antiquity.</p>
<p>What science can present greater attractions than philology? How can a
lover of literary excellence fail to rejoice in the ancient
masterpieces? And with what consistency could I, whose business lies so
much in the attempt to decipher the past and to build up intelligible
forms out of the scattered fragments of long-extinct beings, fail to
take a sympathetic, though an unlearned, interest in the labours of a
Niebuhr, a Gibbon, or a Grote? Classical history is a great section of
the palæontology of man; and I have<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_164" id="Page_164">[Pg 164]</SPAN></span> the same double respect for it as
for other kinds of palæontology—that is to say, a respect for the facts
which it establishes as for all facts, and a still greater respect for
it as a preparation for the discovery of a law of progress.</p>
<p>But if the classics were taught as they might be taught—if boys and
girls were instructed in Greek and Latin, not merely as languages, but
as illustrations of philological science; if a vivid picture of life on
the shores of the Mediterranean two thousand years ago were imprinted on
the minds of scholars; if ancient history were taught, not as a weary
series of feuds and fights, but traced to its causes in such men placed
under such conditions; if, lastly, the study of classical books were
followed in such a manner as to impress boys with their beauties and
with the grand simplicity of their statement of the everlasting problems
of human life, instead of with their verbal and grammatical
peculiarities; I still think it as little proper that they should form
the basis of a liberal education for our contemporaries, as I should
think it fitting to make that sort of palæontology with which I am
familiar the back-bone of modern education.</p>
<p>It is wonderful how close a parallel to classical training could be made
out of that palæontology to which I refer. In the first place I could
get up an osteological primer so arid, so pedantic in its terminology,
so altogether distasteful to the youthful mind, as to beat the recent
famous production of the head-masters out of the field in all<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_165" id="Page_165">[Pg 165]</SPAN></span> these
excellences. Next, I could exercise my boys upon easy fossils and bring
out all their powers of memory and all their ingenuity in the
application of my osteo-grammatical rules to the interpretation, or
construing, of those fragments. To those who had reached the higher
classes, I might supply odd bones to be built up into animals, giving
great honour and reward to him who succeeded in fabricating monsters
most entirely in accordance with the rules. That would answer to
verse-making and essay-writing in the dead languages.</p>
<p>To be sure, if a great comparative anatomist were to look at these
fabrications he might shake his head or laugh. But what then? Would such
a catastrophe destroy the parallel? What, think you, would Cicero or
Horace say to the production of the best sixth form going? And would not
Terence stop his ears and run out if he could be present at an English
performance of his own plays? Would Hamlet, in the mouths of a set of
French actors, who should insist on pronouncing English after the
fashion of their own tongue, be more hideously ridiculous?</p>
<p>But it will be said that I am forgetting the beauty and the human
interest which appertain to classical studies. To this I reply that it
is only a very strong man who can appreciate the charms of a landscape
as he is toiling up a steep hill, along a bad road. What with
short-windedness, stones, ruts and a pervading sense of the wisdom of
rest and be thankful, most of us have little enough<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_166" id="Page_166">[Pg 166]</SPAN></span> sense of the
beautiful under these circumstances. The ordinary schoolboy is precisely
in this case. He finds Parnassus uncommonly steep, and there is no
chance of his having much time or inclination to look about him till he
gets to the top. And nine times out of ten he does not get to the top.</p>
<p>But if this be a fair picture of the results of classical teaching at
its best—and I gather from those who have authority to speak on such
matters that it is so—what is to be said of classical teaching at its
worst, or in other words, of the classics of our ordinary middle-class
schools? I will tell you. It means getting up endless forms and rules by
heart. It means turning Latin and Greek into English, for the mere sake
of being able to do it, and without the smallest regard to the worth, or
worthlessness of the author read. It means the learning of innumerable,
not always decent, fables in such a shape that the meaning they once had
is dried up into utter trash; and the only impression left upon a boy's
mind is, that the people who believed such things must have been the
greatest idiots the world ever saw. And it means, finally, that after a
dozen years spent at this kind of work, the sufferer shall be
incompetent to interpret a passage in an author he has not already got
up; that he shall loathe the sight of a Greek or Latin book; and that he
shall never open, or think of, a classical writer again, until,
wonderful to relate, he insists upon submitting his sons to the same
process.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_167" id="Page_167">[Pg 167]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>Ask the man who is investigating any question profoundly and
thoroughly—be it historical, philosophical, philological, physical,
literary, or theological; who is trying to make himself master of any
abstract subject (except, perhaps, political economy and geology, both
of which are intensely Anglican sciences), whether he is not compelled
to read half a dozen times as many German as English books? And whether,
of these English books, more than one in ten is the work of a fellow of
a college, or a professor of an English university?</p>
<p>Is this from any lack of power in the English as compared with the
German mind? The countrymen of Grote and of Mill, of Faraday, of Robert
Brown, of Lyell and of Darwin, to go no further back than the
contemporaries of men of middle age, can afford to smile at such a
suggestion. England can show now, as she has been able to show in every
generation since civilization spread over the West, individual men who
hold their own against the world, and keep alive the old tradition of
her intellectual eminence.</p>
<p>But, in the majority of cases, these men are what they are in virtue of
their native intellectual force and of a strength of character which
will not recognize impediments. They are not trained in the courts of
the Temple of Science, but storm the walls of that edifice in all sorts
of irregular ways, and with much loss of time and power, in order to
obtain their legitimate positions.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_168" id="Page_168">[Pg 168]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>Our universities not only do not encourage such men; do not offer them
positions in which it should be their highest duty to do, thoroughly,
that which they are most capable of doing; but, as far as possible,
university training shuts out of the minds of those among them, who are
subjected to it, the prospect that there is anything in the world for
which they are specially fitted. Imagine the success of the attempt to
still the intellectual hunger of any of the men I have mentioned, by
putting before him, as the object of existence, the successful mimicry
of the measure of a Greek song, or the roll of Ciceronian prose! Imagine
how much success would be likely to attend the attempt to persuade such
men that the education which leads to perfection in such elegances is
alone to be called culture; while the facts of history, the process of
thought, the conditions of moral and social existence and the laws of
physical nature are left to be dealt with as they may by outside
barbarians!</p>
<p>It is not thus that the German universities, from being beneath notice a
century ago, have become what they are now—the most intensely
cultivated and the most productive intellectual corporations the world
has ever seen.</p>
<p>The student who repairs to them sees in the list of classes and of
professors a fair picture of the world of knowledge. Whatever he needs
to know there is some one ready to teach him, some one competent to
discipline him in the way of learning; whatever his special bent, let
him but<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_169" id="Page_169">[Pg 169]</SPAN></span> be able and diligent, and in due time he shall find distinction
and a career. Among his professors he sees men whose names are known and
revered throughout the civilized world; and their living example infects
him with a noble ambition and a love for the spirit of work.</p>
<p>The Germans dominate the intellectual world by virtue of the same simple
secret as that which made Napoleon the master of old Europe. They have
declared that careers shall be open to talents and every Bursch marches
with a professor's gown in his knapsack. Let him become a great scholar,
or a man of science, and ministers will compete for his services. In
Germany, they do not leave the chance of his holding the office he would
render illustrious to the mercies of a hot canvass and the final wisdom
of a mob of country parsons.</p>
<hr class="tb" />
<p>Moral and social science—one of the greatest and most fruitful of our
future classes, I hope—at present lacks only one thing in our
programme, and that is a teacher. A considerable want, no doubt; but it
must be recollected that it is much better to want a teacher than to
want the desire to learn.</p>
<p>Further, we need what, for want of a better name, I must call Physical
Geography. What I mean is that which the Germans call “<i>Erdkunde</i>.” It
is a description of the earth, of its place and relation to other
bodies; of its general structure and of its great features—winds,
tides, mountains,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_170" id="Page_170">[Pg 170]</SPAN></span> plains: of the chief forms of the vegetable and
animal worlds, of the varieties of man. It is the peg upon which the
greatest quantity of useful and entertaining scientific information can
be suspended.<SPAN name="FNanchor_5_5" id="FNanchor_5_5"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_5_5" class="fnanchor">[5]</SPAN></p>
<p>Literature is not upon the college programme; but I hope some day to see
it there. For literature is the greatest of all sources of refined
pleasure, and one of the great uses of a liberal education is to enable
us to enjoy that pleasure. There is scope enough for the purposes of
liberal education in the study of the rich treasures of our own language
alone. All that is needed is direction, and the cultivation of a refined
taste by attention to sound criticism. But there is no reason why French
and German should not be mastered sufficiently to read what is worth
reading in those languages with pleasure and with profit.</p>
<p>And finally, by-and-by, we must have history; treated not as a
succession of battles and dynasties; not as a series of biographies; not
as evidence that Providence has always been on the side of either Whigs
or Tories, but as the development of man in times past and in other
conditions than our own.</p>
<div class="footnotes"><h3>FOOTNOTES:</h3>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_5_5" id="Footnote_5_5"></SPAN><SPAN href="#FNanchor_5_5"><span class="label">[5]</span></SPAN>Professor Huxley's “Physiography,” published by D. Appleton & Co.,
New York, is an excellent text-book for the study he here recommends. It
has been drawn upon for two chapters of the first volume of
“Masterpieces of Science.” Equally to be recommended are “Physical
Geography” and “Elementary Physical Geography,” by Prof. W. M. Davis, of
Harvard University, published by Ginn & Co., Boston.</p>
</div>
</div>
<hr class="tb" />
<h2 class="nobreak"><SPAN name="SCIENCE_AND_CULTURE" id="SCIENCE_AND_CULTURE"></SPAN>SCIENCE AND CULTURE</h2>
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_171" id="Page_171">[Pg 171]</SPAN></span></p>
<span class="totoc"><SPAN href="#toc">Top</SPAN></span></div>
<h3>PROFESSOR T. H. HUXLEY</h3>
<div class="noteb"> [Sir Josiah Mason's Science College, Birmingham, was opened in 1880
with an address by Professor Huxley which appears in full in the third
volume of his essays published by D. Appleton & Co., New York. As
here given passages of local and temporary interest have been omitted.] </div>
<p>From the time that the first suggestion to introduce physical science
into ordinary education was timidly whispered, until now, the advocates
of scientific education have met with opposition of two kinds. On the
one hand, they have been pooh-poohed by the men of business who pride
themselves on being the representatives of practicality; while, on the
other hand, they have been excommunicated by the classical scholars in
their capacity of Levites in charge of the ark of culture and
monopolists of liberal education.</p>
<p>The practical men believed that the idol whom they worship—rule of
thumb—has been the source of the past prosperity and will suffice for
the future welfare of the arts and manufactures. They were of opinion
that science is speculative rubbish; that theory and practice have
nothing to do with one another; and that the scientific habit of mind is
an impediment, rather than an aid, in the conduct of ordinary affairs.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_172" id="Page_172">[Pg 172]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>I have used the past tense in speaking of the practical men—for
although they were very formidable thirty years ago, I am not sure that
the pure species has not been extirpated. In fact, so far as mere
argument goes, they have been subjected to such a fire from the
netherworld that it is a miracle if any have escaped. But I have
remarked that your typical practical man has an unexpected resemblance
to one of Milton's angels. His spiritual wounds, such as are inflicted
by logical weapons, may be as deep as a well and as wide as a
church-door, but beyond shedding a few drops of ichor, celestial or
otherwise, he is no whit the worse.</p>
<hr class="tb" />
<p>How often have we not been told that the study of physical science is
incompetent to confer culture; that it touches none of the higher
problems of life; and, what is worse, that the continual devotion to
scientific studies tends to generate a narrow and bigoted belief in the
applicability of scientific methods to the search after truth of all
kinds? How frequently one has reason to observe that no reply to a
troublesome argument tells so well as calling its author a “mere
scientific specialist.” And, as I am afraid it is not permissible to
speak of this form of opposition to scientific education in the past
tense; may we not expect to be told that this, not only omission, but
prohibition, of “mere literary instruction and education” is a patent
example of scientific narrow-mindedness?<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_173" id="Page_173">[Pg 173]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>I am not acquainted with Sir Josiah Mason's reasons for declaring that
the college shall make no provision for “mere literary instruction and
education,” but if, as I apprehend the case, he refers to the ordinary
classical course of our schools and universities by the name of “mere
literary instruction and education,” I venture to offer sundry reasons
of my own in support of that action.</p>
<p>For I hold very strongly by two convictions. The first is, that neither
the discipline nor the subject-matter of classical education is of such
direct value to the student of physical science as to justify the
expenditure of valuable time upon either; and the second is, that for
the purpose of attaining real culture, an exclusively scientific
education is at least as effectual as an exclusively literary education.</p>
<p>I need hardly point out to you that these opinions, especially the
latter, are diametrically opposed to those of the great majority of
educated Englishmen, influenced as they are by school and university
traditions. In their belief, culture is obtainable only by a liberal
education; and a liberal education is synonymous, not merely with
education and instruction in literature, but in one particular form of
literature, namely, that of Greek and Roman antiquity. They hold that
the man who has learned Latin and Greek, however little, is educated;
while he who is versed in other branches of knowledge, however deeply,
is a more or less respectable specialist, not admissible<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_174" id="Page_174">[Pg 174]</SPAN></span> into the
cultured caste. The stamp of the educated man, the university degree, is
not for him.</p>
<p>I am too well acquainted with the generous catholicity of spirit, the
true sympathy with scientific thought, which pervades the writings of
our chief apostle of culture to identify him with these opinions; and
yet one may cull from one and another of those epistles to the
Philistines, which so much delight all who do not answer to that name,
sentences which lend them some support.</p>
<p>Mr. Arnold tells us that the meaning of culture is “to know the best
that has been thought and said in the world.” It is the criticism of
life contained in literature. That criticism regards “Europe as being,
for intellectual and spiritual purposes, one great confederation, bound
to a joint action and working to a common result; and whose members
have, for their common outfit, a knowledge of Greek, Roman, and Eastern
antiquity, and of one another. Special, local, and temporary advantages
being put out of account, that modern nation will in the intellectual
and spiritual sphere make most progress, which most thoroughly carries
out this program. And what is that but saying that we too, all of us, as
individuals, the more thoroughly we carry it out, shall make the more
progress?”<SPAN name="FNanchor_6_6" id="FNanchor_6_6"></SPAN><SPAN href="#Footnote_6_6" class="fnanchor">[6]</SPAN></p>
<p>We have here to deal with two distinct propositions. The first, that a
criticism of life is the<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_175" id="Page_175">[Pg 175]</SPAN></span> essence of culture; the second, that
literature contains the materials which suffice for the construction of
such criticism.</p>
<p>I think that we must all assent to the first proposition. For culture
certainly means something quite different from learning or technical
skill. It implies the possession of an ideal, and the habit of
critically estimating the value of things by comparison with a theoretic
standard. Perfect culture should supply a complete theory of life, based
upon a clear knowledge alike of its possibilities and of its
limitations.</p>
<p>But we may agree to all this, and yet strongly dissent from the
assumption that literature alone is competent to supply this knowledge.
After having learnt all that Greek, Roman, and Eastern antiquity have
thought and said, and all that modern literature have to tell us, it is
not self-evident that we have laid a sufficiently broad and deep
foundation for that criticism of life, which constitutes culture.</p>
<p>Indeed, to anyone acquainted with the scope of physical science, it is
not at all evident. Considering progress only in the “intellectual and
spiritual sphere,” I find myself wholly unable to admit that either
nations or individuals will really advance if their common outfit draws
nothing from the stores of physical science. I should say that an army,
without weapons of precision and with no particular base of operations,
might more hopefully enter upon a campaign on the Rhine than a man,
devoid of a knowledge of what physical<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_176" id="Page_176">[Pg 176]</SPAN></span> science has done in the last
century, upon a criticism of life.</p>
<hr class="tb" />
<p>The representatives of the Humanists, in the nineteenth century, take
their stand upon classical education as the sole avenue to culture, as
firmly as if we were still in the age of Renascence. Yet, surely, the
present intellectual relations of the modern and the ancient worlds are
profoundly different from those which obtained three centuries ago.
Leaving aside the existence of a great and characteristically modern
literature, of modern painting, and, especially, of modern music, there
is one feature of the present state of the civilized world which
separates it more widely from the Renascence, than the Renascence was
separated from the middle ages.</p>
<p>This distinctive character of our own times lies in the vast and
constantly increasing part which is played by natural knowledge. Not
only is our daily life shaped by it, not only does the prosperity of
millions of men depend upon it, but our whole theory of life has long
been influenced, consciously or unconsciously, by the general
conceptions of the universe, which have been forced upon us by physical
science.</p>
<p>In fact, the most elementary acquaintance with the results of scientific
investigation shows us that they offer a broad and striking
contradiction to the opinion so implicitly credited and taught in the
middle ages.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_177" id="Page_177">[Pg 177]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>The notions of the beginning and the end of the world entertained by our
forefathers are no longer credible. It is very certain that the earth is
not the chief body in the material universe, and that the world is not
subordinated to man's use. It is even more certain that nature is the
expression of a definite order with which nothing interferes, and that
the chief business of mankind is to learn that order and govern
themselves accordingly. Moreover this scientific “criticism of life”
presents itself to us with different credentials from any other. It
appeals not to authority, nor to what anybody may have thought or said,
but to nature. It admits that all our interpretations of natural fact
are more or less imperfect and symbolic, and bids the learner seek for
truth not among words but among things. It warns us that the assertion
which outstrips evidence is not only a blunder but a crime.</p>
<p>The purely classical education advocated by the representatives of the
Humanists in our day, gives no inkling of all this. A man may be a
better scholar than Erasmus, and know no more of the chief causes of the
present intellectual fermentation than Erasmus did. Scholarly and pious
persons, worthy of all respect, favour us with allocutions upon the
sadness of the antagonism of science to their mediæval way of thinking,
which betray an ignorance of the first principles of scientific
investigation, an incapacity for understanding what a man of science
means by veracity, and an unconsciousness of the weight of established<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_178" id="Page_178">[Pg 178]</SPAN></span>
scientific truths, which is almost comical.</p>
<p>There is no great force in the <i>tu quoque</i> [thou too] argument, or else
the advocates of scientific education might fairly enough retort upon
the modern Humanists that they may be learned specialists, but that they
possess no such sound foundation for a criticism of life as deserves the
name of culture. And, indeed, if we were disposed to be cruel, we might
urge that the Humanists have brought this reproach upon themselves, not
because they are too full of the spirit of the ancient Greek, but
because they lack it.</p>
<p>The period of the Renascence is commonly called that of the “Revival of
Letters,” as if the influences then brought to bear upon the mind of
Western Europe had been wholly exhausted in the field of literature. I
think it is very commonly forgotten that the revival of science,
effected by the same agency, although less conspicuous, was not less
momentous.</p>
<p>In fact, the few and scattered students of nature of that day picked up
the clue to her secrets exactly as it fell from the hands of the Greeks
a thousand years before. The foundations of mathematics were so well
laid by them, that our children learn their geometry from a book written
for the schools of Alexandria two thousand years ago. Modern astronomy
is the natural continuation and development of the work of Hipparchus
and of Ptolemy; modern physics of that of Democritus and of Archimedes<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_179" id="Page_179">[Pg 179]</SPAN></span>.
It was long before modern biological science outgrew the knowledge
bequeathed to us by Aristotle, by Theophrastus, and by Galen.</p>
<p>We cannot know all the best thoughts and sayings of the Greeks unless we
know what they thought about natural phenomena. We cannot fully
apprehend their criticism of life unless we understand the extent to
which that criticism was affected by scientific conceptions. We falsely
pretend to be the inheritors of their culture, unless we are penetrated,
as the best minds among them were, with an unhesitating faith that the
free employment of reason, in accordance with scientific methods, is the
sole method of reaching truth.</p>
<p>Thus I venture to think that the pretensions of our modern Humanists to
the possession of the monopoly of culture and to the exclusive
inheritance of the spirit of antiquity must be abated, if not abandoned.
But I should be very sorry that anything I have said should be taken to
imply a desire on my part to depreciate the value of classical
education, as it might be and as it sometimes is. The native capacities
of mankind vary no less than their opportunities; and while culture is
one, the road by which one man may best reach it is widely different
from that which is most advantageous to another. Again, while scientific
education is yet inchoate and tentative, classical education is
thoroughly well organized upon the practical experience of generations
of teachers.<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_180" id="Page_180">[Pg 180]</SPAN></span></p>
<p>I am the last person to question the importance of genuine literary
education, or to suppose that intellectual culture can be complete
without it. An exclusively scientific training will bring about a mental
twist as surely as an exclusively literary training. The value of the
cargo does not compensate for a ship's being out of trim; and I should
be very sorry to think that the Scientific College would turn out none
but lop-sided men.</p>
<p>There is no need, however, that such a catastrophe should happen.
Instruction in English, French, and German is provided, and thus the
three greatest literatures of the modern world are made accessible to
the student.</p>
<p>French and German, and especially the latter language, are absolutely
indispensable to those who desire full knowledge in any department of
science. But even supposing that the knowledge of these languages
acquired is not more than sufficient for purely scientific purposes,
every Englishman has, in his native tongue, an almost perfect instrument
of literary expression; and, in his own literature, models of every kind
of literary excellence. If an Englishman cannot get literary culture out
of his Bible, his Shakespeare, his Milton, neither, in my belief, will
the profoundest study of Homer and Sophocles, Virgil and Horace, give it
to him.</p>
<p>Thus, since the constitution of the College makes sufficient provision
for literary as well as for scientific education, and since artistic
instruction is also contemplated, it seems to me that a<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_181" id="Page_181">[Pg 181]</SPAN></span> fairly complete
culture is offered to all who are willing to take advantage of it.</p>
<p>But I am not sure that at this point the “practical” man, scotched but
not slain, may ask what all this talk about culture has to do with an
Institution, the object of which is defined to be “to promote the
prosperity of the manufactures and the industry of the country.” He may
suggest that what is wanted for this end is not culture, nor even a
purely scientific discipline, but simply a knowledge of applied science.</p>
<p>I often wish that this phrase, “applied science,” had never been
invented. For it suggests that there is a sort of scientific knowledge
of direct practical use, which can be studied apart from another sort of
scientific knowledge, which is of no practical utility, and which is
termed “pure science.” But there is no more complete fallacy than this.
What people call applied science is nothing but the application of pure
science to particular classes of problems. It consists of deductions
from those general principles, established by reasoning and observation,
which constitute pure science. No one can safely make these deductions
until he has a firm grasp of the principles; and he can obtain that
grasp only by personal experience of the operations of observation and
of reasoning on which they are founded.</p>
<p>Almost all the processes employed in the arts and manufactures fall
within the range either of physics or of chemistry. In order to improve<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_182" id="Page_182">[Pg 182]</SPAN></span>
them, one must thoroughly understand them; and no one has a chance of
really understanding them, unless he has obtained that mastery of
principles and that habit of dealing with facts, which is given by
long-continued and well-directed purely scientific training in the
physical and the chemical laboratory. So that there really is no
question as to the necessity of purely scientific discipline, even if
the work of the College were limited by the narrowest interpretation of
its stated aims.</p>
<p>And, as to the desirableness of a wider culture than that yielded by
science alone, it is to be recollected that the improvement of
manufacturing processes is only one of the conditions which contribute
to the prosperity of industry. Industry is a means and not an end; and
mankind work only to get something which they want. What that something
is depends partly on their innate, and partly on their acquired,
desires.</p>
<p>If the wealth resulting from prosperous industry is to be spent upon the
gratification of unworthy desires, if the increasing perfection of
manufacturing processes is to be accompanied by an increasing debasement
of those who carry them on, I do not see the good of industry and
prosperity.</p>
<p>Now it is perfectly true that men's views of what is desirable depend
upon their characters; and that the innate proclivities to which we give
that name are not touched by any amount of instruction. But it does not
follow that even mere<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_183" id="Page_183">[Pg 183]</SPAN></span> intellectual education may not, to an indefinite
extent, modify the practical manifestation of the characters of men in
their actions, by supplying them with motives unknown to the ignorant. A
pleasure-loving character will have pleasure of some sort; but, if you
give him the choice, he may prefer pleasures which do not degrade him to
those which do. And this choice is offered to every man, who possesses
in literary or artistic culture a never-failing source of pleasures,
which are neither withered by age, nor staled by custom, nor embittered
in the recollection by the pangs of self-reproach.</p>
<p>If the Institution opened to-day fulfils the intention of its founder,
the picked intelligences among all classes of the population of this
district will pass through it. No child born in Birmingham,
henceforward, if he have the capacity to profit by the opportunities
offered to him, first in the primary and other schools, and afterwards
in the Scientific College, need fail to obtain, not merely the
instruction, but the culture most appropriate to the conditions of his
life.</p>
<p>Within these walls, the future employer and the future artisan may
sojourn together for a while, and carry, through all their lives, the
stamp of the influences then brought to bear upon them. Hence, it is not
beside the mark to remind you that the prosperity of industry depends
not merely upon the improvement of manufacturing processes, not merely
upon the ennobling of the individual character, but upon a third
condition,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_184" id="Page_184">[Pg 184]</SPAN></span> namely, a clear understanding of the conditions of social
life, on the part of both the capitalist and the operative, and their
agreement upon common principles of social action. They must learn that
social phenomena are as much the expression of natural laws as any
others; that no social arrangements can be permanent unless they
harmonize with the requirements of social statics and dynamics; and
that, in the nature of things, there is an arbiter whose decisions
execute themselves.</p>
<p>But this knowledge is only to be obtained by the application of the
methods of investigation adopted in physical researches to the
investigation of the phenomena of society. Hence, I confess, I should
like to see one addition made to the excellent scheme of education
propounded for the College, in the shape of provision for the teaching
of Sociology. For though we are all agreed that party politics are to
have no place in the instruction of the College; yet in this country,
practically governed as it is now by universal suffrage, every man who
does his duty must exercise political functions. And, if the evils which
are inseparable from the good of political liberty are to be checked, if
the perpetual oscillation of nations between anarchy and despotism is to
be replaced by the steady march of self-restraining freedom; it will be
because men will gradually bring themselves to deal with political, as
they now deal with scientific questions; to be as ashamed of undue haste
and partisan prejudice in the one case as the other; and to<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_185" id="Page_185">[Pg 185]</SPAN></span> believe
that the machinery of society is at least as delicate as that of a
spinning jenny, and as little likely to be improved by the meddling of
those who have not taken the trouble to master the principles of its
action.</p>
<div class="footnotes"><h3>FOOTNOTES:</h3>
<div class="footnote"><p><SPAN name="Footnote_6_6" id="Footnote_6_6"></SPAN><SPAN href="#FNanchor_6_6"><span class="label">[6]</span></SPAN>“Essays in Criticism,” p. 37.</p>
</div>
</div>
<div class="trans-note">
<h4><span class="smcap">Transcriber's Notes:</span></h4>
<ul>
<li>Page 26—Typo corrected—haye changed to have.</li>
<li>Page 47—Typo corrected—fall changed to falls.</li>
<li>Page 93—Typo corrected—superflous changed to superfluous.</li>
<li>Page 123—Typo corrected—defiinte changed to definite.</li>
<li>Page 155—Typo corrected—removed double word “that”.</li>
<li>Page 170—Typo corrected—sucession changed to succession.</li>
</ul></div>
<SPAN name="endofbook"></SPAN>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />