<h3> CHAPTER IX <br/> CONCLUSION </h3>
<p>I will now briefly sum up the argument of this book.
The problem of truth is to discover the nature of the
agreement between the things of the mind, our ideas,
and the reality of which ideas are the knowledge. We
call the agreement truth. What is it? We have seen
that there are three different answers, namely—(1) That
it is a correspondence between the idea and the reality;
(2) That it is the coherence of the idea in a consistent
and harmonious whole; and (3) That it is a value that
we ourselves give to our ideas.</p>
<p>The theory that truth is correspondence we found to
offer this difficulty. To say of an idea that it
corresponds with reality supposes a knowledge of reality in
addition to and distinct from the knowledge that is the
idea, and yet the knowledge of reality is the idea of it.
And if it be said that not the idea but the judgment
is what corresponds with reality in truth, this equally
supposes a knowledge of reality that is not a judgment.
If, as the common sense of mankind requires us to
believe, the reality that is known by us exists in entire
independence of our relation of knowing to it, how can
we state this fact without falling into contradiction in
the very statement of it? This is the difficulty of a
realist theory of knowledge.</p>
<p>We next examined the theory that truth is coherence,
and this seemed to present to us an unattainable ideal.
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P89"></SPAN>89}</span>
Only the whole truth is wholly true. We followed the
idealist argument on which it is based, and this seemed
to lead us inevitably, in the doctrine of the Absolute,
to the paradox that unless we know everything we
know nothing.</p>
<p>In pragmatism we met a new principle, the proposal
to regard truth as a value. Truth, it is said, is
something that happens to ideas; they become true, or are
made true. There is no criterion, no absolute standard,
independent of ideas to which they must conform if
they are judged to be true. The value of an idea is
its practical usefulness as tested by its workability.
Truth is what works. This led us to criticise the concept
of utility. We found that it is impossible to identify
utility with truth even if we include theoretical utility
in its widest meaning, because over and above the
usefulness and workability of an idea there always
remains the question of its relation to reality. But we
recognised in the principle of truth-value an important
advance towards a theory of knowledge.</p>
<p>The solution of the problem of truth, it became clear,
must be sought in a theory of knowledge. Have we,
in the new theory of life and knowledge of Bergson's
philosophy, an answer to the question, What is truth?
Yes, but not in the form of a direct solution of the
dilemma which confronts us in every theory that
accepts the independence of knowledge and reality—rather
in a theory of knowledge in which the dilemma
does not and cannot arise.</p>
<p>The theory of Bergson is that in the intuition of life
we know reality as it is, our knowledge is one with our
knowing; and in the intellect we possess a mode of
knowing which is equally immediate but the essential
quality of which is that it externalises or spatialises
reality. We understand this mode of knowing in
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P90"></SPAN>90}</span>
recognising the purpose it serves, its practical advantage to
us. The theory, therefore, resembles pragmatism in
bringing the concept of utility to the aid of its theory
of knowledge. But, we insisted, the resemblance is
outward only, for the essential tenet of pragmatism,
that truth itself is a value, is fatal to the theory. It
would mean, in fact, that not the mode of knowing, that
is the intellect, but the actual knowledge itself, is a
practical endowment. But the problem of truth arises
in a new form, for the practical utility of the intellect
consists in the illusion which it produces in us. It
makes the flowing reality appear as fixed states. How,
then, can universal illusion be consistent with the
possession of truth? To answer this question we
examined the nature of illusion and its distinction
from error.</p>
<p>In the last chapter we have dealt with the problem
of error. The fact of error presented a difficulty
distinct from the question, What is truth? for it implied
a real object of thought, of which it seemed equally
contradictory to say that it exists and that it does not
exist. In the solutions that have been proposed we
saw how the problem is forcing philosophers to examine
again the fundamental processes of the mind and the
nature of the universe they reveal.</p>
<p><br/><br/><br/></p>
<p><SPAN name="chap10"></SPAN></p>
<p><span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P91"></SPAN>91}</span></p>
<h3> BIBLIOGRAPHY </h3>
<p>The <i>Theætetus</i> of Plato is an exposition of the problem
of truth and error as it presented itself in ancient
philosophy. The quotation I have made from it, and also
the quotations from the <i>Republic</i>, are from Jowett's
translation.</p>
<p>The most clear exposition of what I have called the
realistic doctrine is <i>The Problems of Philosophy</i>, by the
Hon. Bertrand Russell, in the Home University Library
(Williams and Norgate). I have adopted Mr. Russell's
terms, "acquaintance" and "description"; the distinction
they denote seems to me of fundamental importance,
and Mr. Russell's doctrine on this point a permanent
addition to philosophy. Mr. Russell's theory, that in
the judgment what is present to the mind is a
relation which is external to the terms of the judgment,
and that agreement or disagreement between this
relation and reality makes the truth or falsehood of the
judgment, can only be appreciated if studied in
connection with his general scheme.</p>
<p>The classical work on what I have called the modern
idealist doctrine (I have avoided the word intellectualist)
is Mr. F. H. Bradley's <i>Appearance and Reality</i>. I have
attempted to give the main lines of the theory in my
chapter on "The Absolute." Although it is a book for
advanced students, it is not a closed volume even to
the uninstructed. The brilliant dialectical skill of the
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P92"></SPAN>92}</span>
author is acknowledged and may be enjoyed by those
who reject or may fail to understand his conclusion.
Mr. Harold H. Joachim's <i>The Nature of Truth</i> (Oxford,
Clarendon Press) is a most able and scholarly argument
for the coherence theory of truth.</p>
<p>The principal expositions of Pragmatism are the
works of William James and of Dr. F. C. S. Schiller.
William James' <i>The Will to Believe</i> was the first distinct
formulation of the principle. <i>Pragmatism, a New Name
for some Old Ways of Thinking</i>, is the fullest and most
systematic statement of the doctrine. <i>The Meaning
of Truth</i> is a defence of the doctrine against the criticism
that had been meted out to it unsparingly. All three
books are published by Longmans.</p>
<p>Dr. F. C. S. Schiller is uncompromising in his advocacy
of a complete return to the doctrine taught in the ancient
world by Protagoras. He has defended that philosopher
against the arguments of Plato in a polemical pamphlet
entitled <i>Plato or Protagoras?</i> (Oxford, Blackwell). An
Essay on "Axioms as Postulates" in <i>Personal Idealism</i>
(Macmillan & Co.), and two volumes of collected essays
on <i>Humanism</i> (Macmillan & Co.), set forth the doctrine,
which he prefers to call Humanism, with great force,
abundant illustration, and the relief of no small amount
of humour.</p>
<p>For an account of the theories of Bergson, I may
mention my own little book in this series, <i>Henri Bergson:
The Philosophy of Change</i>. M. Bergson's books are <i>Time
and Freewill</i>, <i>Matter and Memory</i>, and <i>Creative Evolution</i>.
To these has been recently added <i>An Introduction to
Metaphysics</i> (Macmillan, 1912). It is the republication
in English of an article written in 1903, which has been
for a long time out of print. It is a short and clear
statement of the doctrine of Intuition.</p>
<p><span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P93"></SPAN>93}</span></p>
<p>The important studies of Professor G. F. Stout are
not easily accessible to the general reader, as they consist
in contributions to philosophical journals and proceedings
of learned societies. The essay referred to in the
last chapter, "Some Fundamental Points in the Theory
of Knowledge," is in the <i>St. Andrews Quincentenary
Publications</i>, 1911 (Maclehose). I may mention also
his essay on "Error" in <i>Personal Idealism</i>, noticed
above, and "The Object of Thought and Real Being,"
in <i>Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society</i>, 1911.</p>
<p><br/><br/><br/></p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />