<h3> CHAPTER VIII <br/> THE PROBLEM OF ERROR </h3>
<p>In the <i>Theætetus</i> of Plato, Socrates has been discussing
with Theætetus what knowledge is, and when at last
agreement seems to be reached in the definition that
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P75"></SPAN>75}</span>
knowledge is true opinion, a new difficulty occurs to
Socrates:</p>
<p>"There is a point which often troubles me and is a
great perplexity to me both in regard to myself and to
others. I cannot make out the nature or origin of the
mental experience to which I refer. How there can be
false opinion—that difficulty still troubles the eye of
my mind. Do we not speak of false opinion, and say
that one man holds a false and another a true opinion,
as though there were some natural distinction between
them? All things and everything are either known or
not known. He who knows, cannot but know; and he
who does not know, cannot know.... Where, then,
is false opinion? For if all things are either known or
unknown, there can be no opinion which is not comprehended
under this alternative, and so false opinion is
excluded."</p>
<p>This difficulty may appear at first sight purely verbal,
and we shall perhaps be inclined to see the answer to it
in the double use that we make of the word knowledge.
We use the word in two senses, in one of which it
includes all and everything that is or can be present to
the mind in thinking, and in another and narrower
sense the word knowledge means truth. It was in the
narrow sense of the word that whatever is not true is
not knowledge that Socrates interpreted the meaning
of the Delphic oracle that had declared him the wisest
of men. His wisdom must be, he said, that whereas
other men seemed to be wise and to know something,
he knew that he knew nothing. All men have opinion,
but opinion is not knowledge, though easily and
generally mistaken for it. His perplexity was to understand
what actually this false opinion could be which passed
for knowledge. It could not be nothing at all, for then
it would simply mean ignorance; but in false opinion
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P76"></SPAN>76}</span>
some object is present to the mind. Everything that
the mind thinks of has being. A thing may have being
that does not exist if by existence is meant the particular
existence of an event in time, for most of the things we
think about are timeless—they are ideas, such as
whiteness, goodness, numbers and the properties of numbers,
faith, love, and such-like. All such ideas are called
universals, because their reality does not mean that
they exist at one particular moment and no other, but
they are real, they have being. How, then, can there
be anything intermediate between being and not being,
anything that is and also is not, for this is what false
opinion or error seems to be?</p>
<p>There is, then, a problem of error, and it is quite distinct
from the problem of truth. The problem of truth is to
know by what criterion we can test the agreement of
our ideas with reality; the problem of error is to know
how there can be false opinion. There is false opinion,
of this no one needs to be convinced; but where its place
is in the fundamental scheme of the mental process, in
what precisely it consists, whether it is purely a
negation or whether it has a positive nature of its own, this
is the problem we have now to consider.</p>
<p>There is an important distinction in logic between
what is contradictory and what is contrary. Of two
contradictory propositions one must be true, the other
must be false; but of two contrary propositions one
must be false, but both may be false. Of contradictory
propositions one is always a pure negation, one declares
the non-existence of what the other affirms the existence;
but of contrary propositions each has a positive content,
and both may be false. A true proposition may be
based on a false opinion, and it is very important to
have a clear idea of what we intend by false opinion.
We do not mean by false opinion such plainly false
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P77"></SPAN>77}</span>
propositions as that two and two are five or that there
may be no corners in a square—such propositions are
false, because they contradict propositions that are
self-evident. If anyone should seriously affirm them, we
should not, I think, say that such a one had a false
opinion, but that he failed, perhaps through some
illusion, to understand the meaning of the terms he was
using. An example of what would now, I suppose, be
unquestionably regarded by everyone as error is that
whole body of opinion that found expression in the
theory and practice of witchcraft. This was once
almost universally accepted, and though probably at no
period nor in any country was there not some one
who doubted or disbelieved, still the reasons of such
doubt or disbelief would probably be very different
from those reasons which lead us to reject it to-day.
For witchcraft was grounded on a general belief that
spiritual agencies, beneficent and malign, were the cause
of material well-being or evil. This conception has now
given place to the mechanistic or naturalistic theory on
which our modern physical science is based. We
interpret all physical occurrences as caused by material
agency. But this belief, quite as much as the belief in
spiritual agencies, is opinion, not knowledge, and it may
be false. It is conceivable that future generations will
reject our scientific notions, self-evident though they
seem to us, as completely as we reject the notions of
the dark ages. It is even conceivable that the whole
of our modern science may come to appear to mankind
as not even an approximation to knowledge. Error,
like illusion, may be universal. No one whose opinion
counts as a rational belief now holds that sickness may
be caused by the malign influence of the evil eye, and
that this influence may be neutralised by making the
sign of the cross; some, but very few, believe that a
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P78"></SPAN>78}</span>
sick man may be healed by the prayers and anointing
of righteous men; many believe that material disease,
however malignant, may be expelled from the body by
faith; while the majority of rational men, whatever
independent religious views they hold, regard sickness
and disease as material in the ordinary sense, and
expect them to yield to drugs and treatment. Now, of
these various opinions some must be false, while all
may be false. Let us add some illustrations from
philosophy. Some philosophers hold, in common with
general opinion, that sense experience is caused by
physical objects; others hold that there are no physical
objects, but that consciousness is the one and only
reality; and there are others who think that the
reality that gives rise to our sense experience is neither
physical in the sense of a material thing, nor mental
in the sense of consciousness or thought, but is
movement or change—change that requires no support and
is absolute. All these are opinions, and may be false,
and our belief that any one of them is true does not
depend on immediate experience, but on reasons. The
best that can be said in favour of any belief is that
there is no reason for supposing it false, and the worst
that can be said against any belief is that there is no
reason for supposing it true. Our problem, then, is to
know what constitutes the nature of error in any one
of these examples if it is, as each one may be, false?</p>
<p>The instances we have given are all of them propositions
or judgments, or else conceptions formed out of
propositions or judgments, the purpose of which is to
interpret experience. The actual experience itself, in
so far as it consists of the actual presence of the object
to the mind aware of it, is, as we have seen, neither
truth nor error; it simply is what it is. It is the
conceptions by which we interpret this experience that are
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P79"></SPAN>79}</span>
true or false. And our problem is that the meaning or
content of a conception, that which is present to the
mind when we make a judgment, is precisely the same
whether the conception is true or false, there is no
distinctive mark or feature by which we can know that
in the one case the object of thought is a real or actual
fact, in the other an opinion to which no reality
corresponds. And, further, it seems exceedingly difficult to
understand in what way a non-reality can be present
to the mind at all.</p>
<p>Let us now examine some attempts to solve this
problem, and first of all let us take the pragmatist
solution. Pragmatism claims that it has no difficulty
in explaining error, because, as we have already seen,
it acknowledges no other test or criterion of truth except
a pragmatic one. Every proposition or judgment that
we make must, in order to have any meaning whatever,
be relevant to some human purpose; every such
proposition is a truth-claim; and every truth-claim is
tested by its workability. Consequently, error is simply
the failure of a proposition to establish its claim by the
practical test of working. Propositions marked by such
failure are errors. As there is no truth independent of
time, place, and circumstance, no irrelevant truth, no
truth independent of the conditions under which its
claim is put forward, there is no truth that may not
become error. No judgment, according to pragmatism,
is an error pure and simple—that is to say, it cannot
come into existence as error, for it comes claiming
truth, and maintaining that claim until challenged; it
becomes an error in retrospect only, and always in
relation to another judgment which corrects it. Error
does not characterise a class of judgments; it is something
that happens to a judgment, it is a judgment whose
truth-claim is rejected in reference to another judgment
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P80"></SPAN>80}</span>
which succeeds. The essential thing in the pragmatist
doctrine of error is that in claiming to be true a
judgment is not challenging comparison with some independent
reality, nor is it claiming to belong to a timeless
order of existence—to be eternal; it is claiming to fulfil
the particular purpose for which it has been called
forth, whether that purpose be practical or theoretical.</p>
<p>Let us now consider the explanation of error offered
by the idealist philosophy. In this view only the whole
truth is wholly true; the Absolute, as a perfect, concrete,
individual system, is the ideal, and all that falls short of
it can only possess a degree of truth—a degree which
is greater or less according as it approximates to the ideal.
The degrees of truth are not quantitative, not a mixture
of truth and error, but a nearer or more distant approach
to the ideal. There can be no absolute error, because
if truth is the whole, error, if it exists at all, must in
some way be included in truth. Clearly error cannot
as such be truth, and therefore it must follow that, in
the whole, error loses its character of error, and finds
reconciliation of its contradiction to truth. Error,
then, if it is something, and not a pure negation, is partial
or incomplete truth; the perplexity and contradiction
that it gives rise to are incidental to our partial view.
Knowledge, it must seem to us, can exist only for
omniscience. Unless we know everything, we know
nothing.</p>
<p>These two doctrines are in a sense the exact antithesis
of one another. They agree together in this, that
in each the explanation of error follows as a
consequence of the conception of the nature of truth. The
pragmatist theory implies that there is no truth in any
real sense, but only more or less successful error. The
idealist theory implies that there is no real error, but only
a variety in the degree of truth.</p>
<p><span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P81"></SPAN>81}</span></p>
<p>Most people, however, are convinced that truth and
error are not related to one another, nor to the
circumstances that call forth belief or disbelief. Let us now
examine a theory that recognises this. There are false
judgments, and they need explanation; error has a
nature of its own. If a judgment is false, it is absolutely
and unalterably false; if it is true, it is unconditionally
true and with no reserve. No logical process, no
psychological disposition, can make what is false true. Error
must lie in the nature of knowledge, and to discover that
nature we must understand the theory of knowledge
and determine the exact nature of the mental act in
knowing. The first essential is to distinguish the kind
of knowledge to which truth and error can apply. We
pointed out in the second chapter that all knowledge
rests ultimately on immediate experience. In immediate
experience the relation between the mental act of knowing
and the object that is known is so simple that any
question as to truth or error in regard to it is unmeaning.
To question the truth of immediate experience is to
question its existence; it is to ask if it is what it is, and
this is plainly unmeaning. But thinking, we said, is
questioning experience in order to know its content or
meaning, and in thinking, the simplicity of the relation
which unites the mind to its object in immediate
experience is left behind, and a logical process of very
great complexity takes its place. It is in this complexity
that the possibility of error lies.</p>
<p>Let us look at it a little more closely. Knowing is
a relation which unites two things, one the mind that
knows, the other the thing known. In every act of
knowing, something is present to the mind; if knowing
is simply awareness of this actually present something,
we call it immediate experience, we are acquainted with
the object. But our knowledge is not only of objects
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P82"></SPAN>82}</span>
immediately present to the mind and with which we
are therefore acquainted. Knowledge embraces the
past and future and the distant realms of space. Indeed
were knowledge only of what is actually present to the
mind, it is difficult to imagine that we could, in the
ordinary meaning of the word, know anything at all.
I may be thinking, for example, of an absent friend; all
that is present to my mind is, it may be, a memory
image, a faint recall of his appearance on some one
occasion, or perhaps a recollection of the tone of his
voice, or it may be the black marks on white paper
which I recognise as his handwriting. This image is
present to my mind, but the image is not the object,
my friend, about whom I think and make endless
judgments, true and false. So also, if what is present to
the mind is affecting me through the external senses,
if it is a sense impression, it is clear that what is actually
present is not the whole object of which I am aware,
but only a very small part of it, or, it may be, no part
of it at all, but something, a sound, or an odour, that
represents it. The immediate data of consciousness are
named by some philosophers sense data, by others,
presentations, by others images, and there is much
controversy as to their nature and existence, but with
this controversy we are not here concerned—we are
seeking to make clear an obvious distinction, namely,
the distinction between knowledge by acquaintance and
knowledge by description.</p>
<p>What kind of knowledge is it that we acquire by
description? Knowledge about things with which we
are not first acquainted. The most important knowledge
that we possess or acquire is knowledge of objects
which we know only by the knowledge we have about
them—objects that we know about without knowing
them. They are not direct impressions on our senses,
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P83"></SPAN>83}</span>
nor are they ideas known in actual experience. We
make judgments about them, and the subjects about
which we make these judgments are really composed
of these judgments that we make about them. To go
back to our illustrations, we may know a great deal
about the evil eye, a malignant influence, disease, faith,
healing, causality, physical objects, without any
acquaintance with them, without even knowing that they
exist. Such knowledge is descriptive, and the objects
are descriptions. Knowledge by description is never
quite simple, and is often very complex, for, besides the
relation of the mental act to the object known, there
are the terms and relations which are the elements
in the judgment and the relations of the judgments
themselves. If we analyse a judgment, every word
in which it is expressed, whether it is a noun or a
verb or a preposition or a conjunction, conveys a
distinct meaning, indicates a term or a relation, each of
which can be made a distinct object to the mind, and all
of which are combined in the single meaning the judgment
expresses. It is in this complexity that the possibility
of error lies, and the possibility increases as the
complexity increases. All the terms and the relations
which a judgment contains depend on the knowledge
we have by acquaintance—that is to say, we are
ultimately dependent on our actual experience for all
knowledge whatever, whether it is acquaintance or
description, for we can only describe in terms with which
we are acquainted; but in the judgment these elements
are combined into new objects, or a certain relation is
declared to exist between objects, and it is this
combination of the elements of the judgment that involves
its truth or falsehood.</p>
<p>If this view of the nature of the mental act of knowing
is accepted, we are able to understand how false opinion
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P84"></SPAN>84}</span>
is consistent with the fact that all knowledge is truth.
We escape both the alternatives that seemed to Socrates
the only possible ones. "When a man has a false
opinion, does he think that which he knows to be some
other thing which he knows, and knowing both is he at the
same time ignorant of both? Or does he think of
something which he does not know as some other thing which
he does not know?" No, neither; in error he thinks
that something that he knows is in a relation that he
knows to some other thing that he knows, when in fact
that relation is not relating the two things. The false
proposition is not one in which the constituent terms
and relations are unknown or non-existent, but one in
which a combination of these terms and relations is
thought to exist when in fact it does not exist; and the
true proposition is that in which the combination
thought to exist does exist. We can, therefore, if this
account be true, at least know what false opinion or
error can be, whether or not we have any means of
deciding in regard to any particular opinion that it is
false.</p>
<p>There is one other theory, the last we shall notice.
It is in one respect the most important of all, namely,
that it is the most direct attempt to grapple with the
problem of error. It is founded on a theory of
knowledge which we owe mainly to the profound and acute
work of a German philosopher (Meinong), and which
at the present time is being keenly discussed. It is an
attempt to determine more exactly than has yet been
done the fundamental scheme of the mental life and
development. The brief account that I am now offering,
I owe to a paper by Prof. G. F. Stout on "Some
Fundamental Points in the Theory of Knowledge." We have
seen that the problem of error is the difficulty there is
in conceiving how there can be any real thing, any real
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P85"></SPAN>85}</span>
object of thought, intermediate between being and
not-being. Error seems to exist and yet to have a nature
which is a negation of existence, and it seems therefore
to be a downright contradiction when we affirm that
error or false opinion can <i>be</i>—that there is a real object
of thought when we judge falsely. This theory meets
the difficulty directly by distinguishing in the mental
act of knowing a process that is neither perceiving nor
thinking of things, and that involves neither believing
nor disbelieving on the one hand nor desiring or willing
on the other: this is the process of supposing.
Corresponding to this mental act of supposing, there is a
distinct kind of object intended or meant by the mind—an
object that is neither a sense datum nor an idea,
nor a judgment, but a supposition. Also and again
corresponding to this mental act of supposing and its
intended object the supposition, there is a mode of
being which is neither existence nor non-existence, but
is named subsistence. A supposition, it is said, does not
exist—it subsists. This thesis, it will easily be
understood, is based on an analysis, and deals with arguments
that touch the most fundamental problems of theory
of knowledge. Moreover, its presentment is excessively
technical, and only those highly trained in the habit of
psychological introspection and skilled in philosophical
analysis are really competent to discuss it. It is not
possible to offer here anything but a simple outline of
the part of the theory that concerns the present problem.
The actual experience of knowing is a relation between
two things, one of which is a mental <i>act</i>, the act of
perceiving or thinking or having ideas, and the other is
an <i>object</i>, that which is perceived or thought of. The
act is a particular mental existence, it is the act of a
psychical individual. The object is not included within
the actual experience which is the knowing of it, it is
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P86"></SPAN>86}</span>
that which is meant or intended by the experience.
The act, then, is the mental process of meaning or
intending, the object the thing meant or intended. The
mental act differs according to the kind of object
intended. The act of perceiving is the direction of the
mind towards sense data and ideas; the act of judging
is the direction of the mind towards judgments or
propositions about things, propositions that affirm or
deny relations between things; the act of supposing
is different from both these—it is the direction of the
mind towards suppositions. Suppositions differ from
ideas in this, that they may be either positive or
negative, whereas ideas are never negative. This may seem
to contradict experience. Can we not, for example,
have an idea of not-red just as well as an idea of red?
No, the two ideas can easily be seen to be one and the
same; in each case it is red we are actually acquainted
with, and the difference is in affirming or denying
existence to the one idea. The difference is in our
judgment, which may be affirmative or negative. A
supposition is like a judgment in this respect; it may be
either affirmative or negative, but it differs from a
judgment in another respect, that while a judgment always
conveys a conviction, always expresses belief or
disbelief, a supposition does not—it is neither believed nor
disbelieved.</p>
<p>Before I show the application of this analysis of
knowledge to the problem of error, let me try and clear
up its obscurity, for undoubtedly it is difficult to
comprehend. Its difficulty lies in this, that though all the
ideas with which it deals are quite familiar—suppositions,
real and unreal possibilities, fulfilled and non-fulfilled
beliefs—yet it seems to run counter to all our
notions of the extreme simplicity of the appeal to reality.
It seems strange and paradoxical to our ordinary habit
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P87"></SPAN>87}</span>
of thinking to affirm that there are real things and real
relations between things which though real yet do not
exist, and also that non-existent realities are not things
that once were real but now are nought—they are things
that subsist. Yet this is no new doctrine. The most
familiar case of such realities is that of numbers. The
Greeks discovered that numbers do not exist—that is to
say, that their reality is of another kind to that which
we denote by existence. Numbers are realities,
otherwise there would be no science of mathematics.
Pythagoras (about 540-500 B.C.) taught that numbers are the
reality from which all else is derived. And there are
many other things of the mind that seem indeed to be
more real than the things of sense. It is this very
problem of error that brings into relief this most
important doctrine.</p>
<p>Now let us apply this theory of the supposition to the
problem of error, and we shall then see how there can
be an object present to the mind when we judge falsely,
and also that the object is the same whether we judge
truly or falsely. Suppositions are real possibilities;
they are alternatives that may be fulfilled or that may
never be fulfilled. These real possibilities, or these
possible alternatives, are objects of thought; they do
not belong to the mental act of thinking; they are not
in the mind, but realities present to the mind. In mere
supposing they are present as alternatives; in judging,
we affirm of them or deny of them the relation to general
reality that they are fulfilled. Judgments therefore
are true or false accordingly as the fulfilment they affirm
does or does not agree with reality. In this way, then,
we may answer the perplexing question, How can there
be an object of thought in a false judgment? The
answer is, that the objects of thought about which we
make judgments are suppositions, and our judgments
<span class="pagenum">{<SPAN name="P88"></SPAN>88}</span>
concern their fulfilment, and their fulfilment is a relation
external to them—it is their agreement or disagreement
with reality.</p>
<p><br/><br/><br/></p>
<p><SPAN name="chap09"></SPAN></p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />