<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0006" id="link2HCH0006"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER VI. WE SCHOLARS </h2>
<p>204. At the risk that moralizing may also reveal itself here as that which
it has always been—namely, resolutely MONTRER SES PLAIES, according
to Balzac—I would venture to protest against an improper and
injurious alteration of rank, which quite unnoticed, and as if with the
best conscience, threatens nowadays to establish itself in the relations
of science and philosophy. I mean to say that one must have the right out
of one's own EXPERIENCE—experience, as it seems to me, always
implies unfortunate experience?—to treat of such an important
question of rank, so as not to speak of colour like the blind, or AGAINST
science like women and artists ("Ah! this dreadful science!" sigh their
instinct and their shame, "it always FINDS THINGS OUT!"). The declaration
of independence of the scientific man, his emancipation from philosophy,
is one of the subtler after-effects of democratic organization and
disorganization: the self-glorification and self-conceitedness of the
learned man is now everywhere in full bloom, and in its best springtime—which
does not mean to imply that in this case self-praise smells sweet. Here
also the instinct of the populace cries, "Freedom from all masters!" and
after science has, with the happiest results, resisted theology, whose
"hand-maid" it had been too long, it now proposes in its wantonness and
indiscretion to lay down laws for philosophy, and in its turn to play the
"master"—what am I saying! to play the PHILOSOPHER on its own
account. My memory—the memory of a scientific man, if you please!—teems
with the naivetes of insolence which I have heard about philosophy and
philosophers from young naturalists and old physicians (not to mention the
most cultured and most conceited of all learned men, the philologists and
schoolmasters, who are both the one and the other by profession). On one
occasion it was the specialist and the Jack Horner who instinctively stood
on the defensive against all synthetic tasks and capabilities; at another
time it was the industrious worker who had got a scent of OTIUM and
refined luxuriousness in the internal economy of the philosopher, and felt
himself aggrieved and belittled thereby. On another occasion it was the
colour-blindness of the utilitarian, who sees nothing in philosophy but a
series of REFUTED systems, and an extravagant expenditure which "does
nobody any good". At another time the fear of disguised mysticism and of
the boundary-adjustment of knowledge became conspicuous, at another time
the disregard of individual philosophers, which had involuntarily extended
to disregard of philosophy generally. In fine, I found most frequently,
behind the proud disdain of philosophy in young scholars, the evil
after-effect of some particular philosopher, to whom on the whole
obedience had been foresworn, without, however, the spell of his scornful
estimates of other philosophers having been got rid of—the result
being a general ill-will to all philosophy. (Such seems to me, for
instance, the after-effect of Schopenhauer on the most modern Germany: by
his unintelligent rage against Hegel, he has succeeded in severing the
whole of the last generation of Germans from its connection with German
culture, which culture, all things considered, has been an elevation and a
divining refinement of the HISTORICAL SENSE, but precisely at this point
Schopenhauer himself was poor, irreceptive, and un-German to the extent of
ingeniousness.) On the whole, speaking generally, it may just have been
the humanness, all-too-humanness of the modern philosophers themselves, in
short, their contemptibleness, which has injured most radically the
reverence for philosophy and opened the doors to the instinct of the
populace. Let it but be acknowledged to what an extent our modern world
diverges from the whole style of the world of Heraclitus, Plato,
Empedocles, and whatever else all the royal and magnificent anchorites of
the spirit were called, and with what justice an honest man of science MAY
feel himself of a better family and origin, in view of such
representatives of philosophy, who, owing to the fashion of the present
day, are just as much aloft as they are down below—in Germany, for
instance, the two lions of Berlin, the anarchist Eugen Duhring and the
amalgamist Eduard von Hartmann. It is especially the sight of those
hotch-potch philosophers, who call themselves "realists," or
"positivists," which is calculated to implant a dangerous distrust in the
soul of a young and ambitious scholar those philosophers, at the best, are
themselves but scholars and specialists, that is very evident! All of them
are persons who have been vanquished and BROUGHT BACK AGAIN under the
dominion of science, who at one time or another claimed more from
themselves, without having a right to the "more" and its responsibility—and
who now, creditably, rancorously, and vindictively, represent in word and
deed, DISBELIEF in the master-task and supremacy of philosophy After all,
how could it be otherwise? Science flourishes nowadays and has the good
conscience clearly visible on its countenance, while that to which the
entire modern philosophy has gradually sunk, the remnant of philosophy of
the present day, excites distrust and displeasure, if not scorn and pity
Philosophy reduced to a "theory of knowledge," no more in fact than a
diffident science of epochs and doctrine of forbearance a philosophy that
never even gets beyond the threshold, and rigorously DENIES itself the
right to enter—that is philosophy in its last throes, an end, an
agony, something that awakens pity. How could such a philosophy—RULE!</p>
<p>205. The dangers that beset the evolution of the philosopher are, in fact,
so manifold nowadays, that one might doubt whether this fruit could still
come to maturity. The extent and towering structure of the sciences have
increased enormously, and therewith also the probability that the
philosopher will grow tired even as a learner, or will attach himself
somewhere and "specialize" so that he will no longer attain to his
elevation, that is to say, to his superspection, his circumspection, and
his DESPECTION. Or he gets aloft too late, when the best of his maturity
and strength is past, or when he is impaired, coarsened, and deteriorated,
so that his view, his general estimate of things, is no longer of much
importance. It is perhaps just the refinement of his intellectual
conscience that makes him hesitate and linger on the way, he dreads the
temptation to become a dilettante, a millepede, a milleantenna, he knows
too well that as a discerner, one who has lost his self-respect no longer
commands, no longer LEADS, unless he should aspire to become a great
play-actor, a philosophical Cagliostro and spiritual rat-catcher—in
short, a misleader. This is in the last instance a question of taste, if
it has not really been a question of conscience. To double once more the
philosopher's difficulties, there is also the fact that he demands from
himself a verdict, a Yea or Nay, not concerning science, but concerning
life and the worth of life—he learns unwillingly to believe that it
is his right and even his duty to obtain this verdict, and he has to seek
his way to the right and the belief only through the most extensive
(perhaps disturbing and destroying) experiences, often hesitating,
doubting, and dumbfounded. In fact, the philosopher has long been mistaken
and confused by the multitude, either with the scientific man and ideal
scholar, or with the religiously elevated, desensualized, desecularized
visionary and God-intoxicated man; and even yet when one hears anybody
praised, because he lives "wisely," or "as a philosopher," it hardly means
anything more than "prudently and apart." Wisdom: that seems to the
populace to be a kind of flight, a means and artifice for withdrawing
successfully from a bad game; but the GENUINE philosopher—does it
not seem so to US, my friends?—lives "unphilosophically" and
"unwisely," above all, IMPRUDENTLY, and feels the obligation and burden of
a hundred attempts and temptations of life—he risks HIMSELF
constantly, he plays THIS bad game.</p>
<p>206. In relation to the genius, that is to say, a being who either
ENGENDERS or PRODUCES—both words understood in their fullest sense—the
man of learning, the scientific average man, has always something of the
old maid about him; for, like her, he is not conversant with the two
principal functions of man. To both, of course, to the scholar and to the
old maid, one concedes respectability, as if by way of indemnification—in
these cases one emphasizes the respectability—and yet, in the
compulsion of this concession, one has the same admixture of vexation. Let
us examine more closely: what is the scientific man? Firstly, a
commonplace type of man, with commonplace virtues: that is to say, a
non-ruling, non-authoritative, and non-self-sufficient type of man; he
possesses industry, patient adaptableness to rank and file, equability and
moderation in capacity and requirement; he has the instinct for people
like himself, and for that which they require—for instance: the
portion of independence and green meadow without which there is no rest
from labour, the claim to honour and consideration (which first and
foremost presupposes recognition and recognisability), the sunshine of a
good name, the perpetual ratification of his value and usefulness, with
which the inward DISTRUST which lies at the bottom of the heart of all
dependent men and gregarious animals, has again and again to be overcome.
The learned man, as is appropriate, has also maladies and faults of an
ignoble kind: he is full of petty envy, and has a lynx-eye for the weak
points in those natures to whose elevations he cannot attain. He is
confiding, yet only as one who lets himself go, but does not FLOW; and
precisely before the man of the great current he stands all the colder and
more reserved—his eye is then like a smooth and irresponsive lake,
which is no longer moved by rapture or sympathy. The worst and most
dangerous thing of which a scholar is capable results from the instinct of
mediocrity of his type, from the Jesuitism of mediocrity, which labours
instinctively for the destruction of the exceptional man, and endeavours
to break—or still better, to relax—every bent bow To relax, of
course, with consideration, and naturally with an indulgent hand—to
RELAX with confiding sympathy that is the real art of Jesuitism, which has
always understood how to introduce itself as the religion of sympathy.</p>
<p>207. However gratefully one may welcome the OBJECTIVE spirit—and who
has not been sick to death of all subjectivity and its confounded
IPSISIMOSITY!—in the end, however, one must learn caution even with
regard to one's gratitude, and put a stop to the exaggeration with which
the unselfing and depersonalizing of the spirit has recently been
celebrated, as if it were the goal in itself, as if it were salvation and
glorification—as is especially accustomed to happen in the pessimist
school, which has also in its turn good reasons for paying the highest
honours to "disinterested knowledge" The objective man, who no longer
curses and scolds like the pessimist, the IDEAL man of learning in whom
the scientific instinct blossoms forth fully after a thousand complete and
partial failures, is assuredly one of the most costly instruments that
exist, but his place is in the hand of one who is more powerful He is only
an instrument, we may say, he is a MIRROR—he is no "purpose in
himself" The objective man is in truth a mirror accustomed to prostration
before everything that wants to be known, with such desires only as
knowing or "reflecting" implies—he waits until something comes, and
then expands himself sensitively, so that even the light footsteps and
gliding-past of spiritual beings may not be lost on his surface and film
Whatever "personality" he still possesses seems to him accidental,
arbitrary, or still oftener, disturbing, so much has he come to regard
himself as the passage and reflection of outside forms and events He calls
up the recollection of "himself" with an effort, and not infrequently
wrongly, he readily confounds himself with other persons, he makes
mistakes with regard to his own needs, and here only is he unrefined and
negligent Perhaps he is troubled about the health, or the pettiness and
confined atmosphere of wife and friend, or the lack of companions and
society—indeed, he sets himself to reflect on his suffering, but in
vain! His thoughts already rove away to the MORE GENERAL case, and
tomorrow he knows as little as he knew yesterday how to help himself He
does not now take himself seriously and devote time to himself he is
serene, NOT from lack of trouble, but from lack of capacity for grasping
and dealing with HIS trouble The habitual complaisance with respect to all
objects and experiences, the radiant and impartial hospitality with which
he receives everything that comes his way, his habit of inconsiderate
good-nature, of dangerous indifference as to Yea and Nay: alas! there are
enough of cases in which he has to atone for these virtues of his!—and
as man generally, he becomes far too easily the CAPUT MORTUUM of such
virtues. Should one wish love or hatred from him—I mean love and
hatred as God, woman, and animal understand them—he will do what he
can, and furnish what he can. But one must not be surprised if it should
not be much—if he should show himself just at this point to be
false, fragile, questionable, and deteriorated. His love is constrained,
his hatred is artificial, and rather UN TOUR DE FORCE, a slight
ostentation and exaggeration. He is only genuine so far as he can be
objective; only in his serene totality is he still "nature" and "natural."
His mirroring and eternally self-polishing soul no longer knows how to
affirm, no longer how to deny; he does not command; neither does he
destroy. "JE NE MEPRISE PRESQUE RIEN"—he says, with Leibniz: let us
not overlook nor undervalue the PRESQUE! Neither is he a model man; he
does not go in advance of any one, nor after, either; he places himself
generally too far off to have any reason for espousing the cause of either
good or evil. If he has been so long confounded with the PHILOSOPHER, with
the Caesarian trainer and dictator of civilization, he has had far too
much honour, and what is more essential in him has been overlooked—he
is an instrument, something of a slave, though certainly the sublimest
sort of slave, but nothing in himself—PRESQUE RIEN! The objective
man is an instrument, a costly, easily injured, easily tarnished measuring
instrument and mirroring apparatus, which is to be taken care of and
respected; but he is no goal, not outgoing nor upgoing, no complementary
man in whom the REST of existence justifies itself, no termination—and
still less a commencement, an engendering, or primary cause, nothing
hardy, powerful, self-centred, that wants to be master; but rather only a
soft, inflated, delicate, movable potter's-form, that must wait for some
kind of content and frame to "shape" itself thereto—for the most
part a man without frame and content, a "selfless" man. Consequently,
also, nothing for women, IN PARENTHESI.</p>
<p>208. When a philosopher nowadays makes known that he is not a skeptic—I
hope that has been gathered from the foregoing description of the
objective spirit?—people all hear it impatiently; they regard him on
that account with some apprehension, they would like to ask so many, many
questions... indeed among timid hearers, of whom there are now so many, he
is henceforth said to be dangerous. With his repudiation of skepticism, it
seems to them as if they heard some evil-threatening sound in the
distance, as if a new kind of explosive were being tried somewhere, a
dynamite of the spirit, perhaps a newly discovered Russian NIHILINE, a
pessimism BONAE VOLUNTATIS, that not only denies, means denial, but—dreadful
thought! PRACTISES denial. Against this kind of "good-will"—a will
to the veritable, actual negation of life—there is, as is generally
acknowledged nowadays, no better soporific and sedative than skepticism,
the mild, pleasing, lulling poppy of skepticism; and Hamlet himself is now
prescribed by the doctors of the day as an antidote to the "spirit," and
its underground noises. "Are not our ears already full of bad sounds?" say
the skeptics, as lovers of repose, and almost as a kind of safety police;
"this subterranean Nay is terrible! Be still, ye pessimistic moles!" The
skeptic, in effect, that delicate creature, is far too easily frightened;
his conscience is schooled so as to start at every Nay, and even at that
sharp, decided Yea, and feels something like a bite thereby. Yea! and Nay!—they
seem to him opposed to morality; he loves, on the contrary, to make a
festival to his virtue by a noble aloofness, while perhaps he says with
Montaigne: "What do I know?" Or with Socrates: "I know that I know
nothing." Or: "Here I do not trust myself, no door is open to me." Or:
"Even if the door were open, why should I enter immediately?" Or: "What is
the use of any hasty hypotheses? It might quite well be in good taste to
make no hypotheses at all. Are you absolutely obliged to straighten at
once what is crooked? to stuff every hole with some kind of oakum? Is
there not time enough for that? Has not the time leisure? Oh, ye demons,
can ye not at all WAIT? The uncertain also has its charms, the Sphinx,
too, is a Circe, and Circe, too, was a philosopher."—Thus does a
skeptic console himself; and in truth he needs some consolation. For
skepticism is the most spiritual expression of a certain many-sided
physiological temperament, which in ordinary language is called nervous
debility and sickliness; it arises whenever races or classes which have
been long separated, decisively and suddenly blend with one another. In
the new generation, which has inherited as it were different standards and
valuations in its blood, everything is disquiet, derangement, doubt, and
tentativeness; the best powers operate restrictively, the very virtues
prevent each other growing and becoming strong, equilibrium, ballast, and
perpendicular stability are lacking in body and soul. That, however, which
is most diseased and degenerated in such nondescripts is the WILL; they
are no longer familiar with independence of decision, or the courageous
feeling of pleasure in willing—they are doubtful of the "freedom of
the will" even in their dreams Our present-day Europe, the scene of a
senseless, precipitate attempt at a radical blending of classes, and
CONSEQUENTLY of races, is therefore skeptical in all its heights and
depths, sometimes exhibiting the mobile skepticism which springs
impatiently and wantonly from branch to branch, sometimes with gloomy
aspect, like a cloud over-charged with interrogative signs—and often
sick unto death of its will! Paralysis of will, where do we not find this
cripple sitting nowadays! And yet how bedecked oftentimes' How seductively
ornamented! There are the finest gala dresses and disguises for this
disease, and that, for instance, most of what places itself nowadays in
the show-cases as "objectiveness," "the scientific spirit," "L'ART POUR
L'ART," and "pure voluntary knowledge," is only decked-out skepticism and
paralysis of will—I am ready to answer for this diagnosis of the
European disease—The disease of the will is diffused unequally over
Europe, it is worst and most varied where civilization has longest
prevailed, it decreases according as "the barbarian" still—or again—asserts
his claims under the loose drapery of Western culture It is therefore in
the France of today, as can be readily disclosed and comprehended, that
the will is most infirm, and France, which has always had a masterly
aptitude for converting even the portentous crises of its spirit into
something charming and seductive, now manifests emphatically its
intellectual ascendancy over Europe, by being the school and exhibition of
all the charms of skepticism The power to will and to persist, moreover,
in a resolution, is already somewhat stronger in Germany, and again in the
North of Germany it is stronger than in Central Germany, it is
considerably stronger in England, Spain, and Corsica, associated with
phlegm in the former and with hard skulls in the latter—not to
mention Italy, which is too young yet to know what it wants, and must
first show whether it can exercise will, but it is strongest and most
surprising of all in that immense middle empire where Europe as it were
flows back to Asia—namely, in Russia There the power to will has
been long stored up and accumulated, there the will—uncertain
whether to be negative or affirmative—waits threateningly to be
discharged (to borrow their pet phrase from our physicists) Perhaps not
only Indian wars and complications in Asia would be necessary to free
Europe from its greatest danger, but also internal subversion, the
shattering of the empire into small states, and above all the introduction
of parliamentary imbecility, together with the obligation of every one to
read his newspaper at breakfast I do not say this as one who desires it,
in my heart I should rather prefer the contrary—I mean such an
increase in the threatening attitude of Russia, that Europe would have to
make up its mind to become equally threatening—namely, TO ACQUIRE
ONE WILL, by means of a new caste to rule over the Continent, a
persistent, dreadful will of its own, that can set its aims thousands of
years ahead; so that the long spun-out comedy of its petty-statism, and
its dynastic as well as its democratic many-willed-ness, might finally be
brought to a close. The time for petty politics is past; the next century
will bring the struggle for the dominion of the world—the COMPULSION
to great politics.</p>
<p>209. As to how far the new warlike age on which we Europeans have
evidently entered may perhaps favour the growth of another and stronger
kind of skepticism, I should like to express myself preliminarily merely
by a parable, which the lovers of German history will already understand.
That unscrupulous enthusiast for big, handsome grenadiers (who, as King of
Prussia, brought into being a military and skeptical genius—and
therewith, in reality, the new and now triumphantly emerged type of
German), the problematic, crazy father of Frederick the Great, had on one
point the very knack and lucky grasp of the genius: he knew what was then
lacking in Germany, the want of which was a hundred times more alarming
and serious than any lack of culture and social form—his ill-will to
the young Frederick resulted from the anxiety of a profound instinct. MEN
WERE LACKING; and he suspected, to his bitterest regret, that his own son
was not man enough. There, however, he deceived himself; but who would not
have deceived himself in his place? He saw his son lapsed to atheism, to
the ESPRIT, to the pleasant frivolity of clever Frenchmen—he saw in
the background the great bloodsucker, the spider skepticism; he suspected
the incurable wretchedness of a heart no longer hard enough either for
evil or good, and of a broken will that no longer commands, is no longer
ABLE to command. Meanwhile, however, there grew up in his son that new
kind of harder and more dangerous skepticism—who knows TO WHAT
EXTENT it was encouraged just by his father's hatred and the icy
melancholy of a will condemned to solitude?—the skepticism of daring
manliness, which is closely related to the genius for war and conquest,
and made its first entrance into Germany in the person of the great
Frederick. This skepticism despises and nevertheless grasps; it undermines
and takes possession; it does not believe, but it does not thereby lose
itself; it gives the spirit a dangerous liberty, but it keeps strict guard
over the heart. It is the GERMAN form of skepticism, which, as a continued
Fredericianism, risen to the highest spirituality, has kept Europe for a
considerable time under the dominion of the German spirit and its critical
and historical distrust Owing to the insuperably strong and tough
masculine character of the great German philologists and historical
critics (who, rightly estimated, were also all of them artists of
destruction and dissolution), a NEW conception of the German spirit
gradually established itself—in spite of all Romanticism in music
and philosophy—in which the leaning towards masculine skepticism was
decidedly prominent whether, for instance, as fearlessness of gaze, as
courage and sternness of the dissecting hand, or as resolute will to
dangerous voyages of discovery, to spiritualized North Pole expeditions
under barren and dangerous skies. There may be good grounds for it when
warm-blooded and superficial humanitarians cross themselves before this
spirit, CET ESPRIT FATALISTE, IRONIQUE, MEPHISTOPHELIQUE, as Michelet
calls it, not without a shudder. But if one would realize how
characteristic is this fear of the "man" in the German spirit which
awakened Europe out of its "dogmatic slumber," let us call to mind the
former conception which had to be overcome by this new one—and that
it is not so very long ago that a masculinized woman could dare, with
unbridled presumption, to recommend the Germans to the interest of Europe
as gentle, good-hearted, weak-willed, and poetical fools. Finally, let us
only understand profoundly enough Napoleon's astonishment when he saw
Goethe it reveals what had been regarded for centuries as the "German
spirit" "VOILA UN HOMME!"—that was as much as to say "But this is a
MAN! And I only expected to see a German!"</p>
<p>210. Supposing, then, that in the picture of the philosophers of the
future, some trait suggests the question whether they must not perhaps be
skeptics in the last-mentioned sense, something in them would only be
designated thereby—and not they themselves. With equal right they
might call themselves critics, and assuredly they will be men of
experiments. By the name with which I ventured to baptize them, I have
already expressly emphasized their attempting and their love of attempting
is this because, as critics in body and soul, they will love to make use
of experiments in a new, and perhaps wider and more dangerous sense? In
their passion for knowledge, will they have to go further in daring and
painful attempts than the sensitive and pampered taste of a democratic
century can approve of?—There is no doubt these coming ones will be
least able to dispense with the serious and not unscrupulous qualities
which distinguish the critic from the skeptic I mean the certainty as to
standards of worth, the conscious employment of a unity of method, the
wary courage, the standing-alone, and the capacity for
self-responsibility, indeed, they will avow among themselves a DELIGHT in
denial and dissection, and a certain considerate cruelty, which knows how
to handle the knife surely and deftly, even when the heart bleeds They
will be STERNER (and perhaps not always towards themselves only) than
humane people may desire, they will not deal with the "truth" in order
that it may "please" them, or "elevate" and "inspire" them—they will
rather have little faith in "TRUTH" bringing with it such revels for the
feelings. They will smile, those rigorous spirits, when any one says in
their presence "That thought elevates me, why should it not be true?" or
"That work enchants me, why should it not be beautiful?" or "That artist
enlarges me, why should he not be great?" Perhaps they will not only have
a smile, but a genuine disgust for all that is thus rapturous, idealistic,
feminine, and hermaphroditic, and if any one could look into their inmost
hearts, he would not easily find therein the intention to reconcile
"Christian sentiments" with "antique taste," or even with "modern
parliamentarism" (the kind of reconciliation necessarily found even among
philosophers in our very uncertain and consequently very conciliatory
century). Critical discipline, and every habit that conduces to purity and
rigour in intellectual matters, will not only be demanded from themselves
by these philosophers of the future, they may even make a display thereof
as their special adornment—nevertheless they will not want to be
called critics on that account. It will seem to them no small indignity to
philosophy to have it decreed, as is so welcome nowadays, that "philosophy
itself is criticism and critical science—and nothing else whatever!"
Though this estimate of philosophy may enjoy the approval of all the
Positivists of France and Germany (and possibly it even flattered the
heart and taste of KANT: let us call to mind the titles of his principal
works), our new philosophers will say, notwithstanding, that critics are
instruments of the philosopher, and just on that account, as instruments,
they are far from being philosophers themselves! Even the great Chinaman
of Konigsberg was only a great critic.</p>
<p>211. I insist upon it that people finally cease confounding philosophical
workers, and in general scientific men, with philosophers—that
precisely here one should strictly give "each his own," and not give those
far too much, these far too little. It may be necessary for the education
of the real philosopher that he himself should have once stood upon all
those steps upon which his servants, the scientific workers of philosophy,
remain standing, and MUST remain standing he himself must perhaps have
been critic, and dogmatist, and historian, and besides, poet, and
collector, and traveler, and riddle-reader, and moralist, and seer, and
"free spirit," and almost everything, in order to traverse the whole range
of human values and estimations, and that he may BE ABLE with a variety of
eyes and consciences to look from a height to any distance, from a depth
up to any height, from a nook into any expanse. But all these are only
preliminary conditions for his task; this task itself demands something
else—it requires him TO CREATE VALUES. The philosophical workers,
after the excellent pattern of Kant and Hegel, have to fix and formalize
some great existing body of valuations—that is to say, former
DETERMINATIONS OF VALUE, creations of value, which have become prevalent,
and are for a time called "truths"—whether in the domain of the
LOGICAL, the POLITICAL (moral), or the ARTISTIC. It is for these
investigators to make whatever has happened and been esteemed hitherto,
conspicuous, conceivable, intelligible, and manageable, to shorten
everything long, even "time" itself, and to SUBJUGATE the entire past: an
immense and wonderful task, in the carrying out of which all refined
pride, all tenacious will, can surely find satisfaction. THE REAL
PHILOSOPHERS, HOWEVER, ARE COMMANDERS AND LAW-GIVERS; they say: "Thus
SHALL it be!" They determine first the Whither and the Why of mankind, and
thereby set aside the previous labour of all philosophical workers, and
all subjugators of the past—they grasp at the future with a creative
hand, and whatever is and was, becomes for them thereby a means, an
instrument, and a hammer. Their "knowing" is CREATING, their creating is a
law-giving, their will to truth is—WILL TO POWER.—Are there at
present such philosophers? Have there ever been such philosophers? MUST
there not be such philosophers some day? ...</p>
<p>212. It is always more obvious to me that the philosopher, as a man
INDISPENSABLE for the morrow and the day after the morrow, has ever found
himself, and HAS BEEN OBLIGED to find himself, in contradiction to the day
in which he lives; his enemy has always been the ideal of his day.
Hitherto all those extraordinary furtherers of humanity whom one calls
philosophers—who rarely regarded themselves as lovers of wisdom, but
rather as disagreeable fools and dangerous interrogators—have found
their mission, their hard, involuntary, imperative mission (in the end,
however, the greatness of their mission), in being the bad conscience of
their age. In putting the vivisector's knife to the breast of the very
VIRTUES OF THEIR AGE, they have betrayed their own secret; it has been for
the sake of a NEW greatness of man, a new untrodden path to his
aggrandizement. They have always disclosed how much hypocrisy, indolence,
self-indulgence, and self-neglect, how much falsehood was concealed under
the most venerated types of contemporary morality, how much virtue was
OUTLIVED, they have always said "We must remove hence to where YOU are
least at home" In the face of a world of "modern ideas," which would like
to confine every one in a corner, in a "specialty," a philosopher, if
there could be philosophers nowadays, would be compelled to place the
greatness of man, the conception of "greatness," precisely in his
comprehensiveness and multifariousness, in his all-roundness, he would
even determine worth and rank according to the amount and variety of that
which a man could bear and take upon himself, according to the EXTENT to
which a man could stretch his responsibility Nowadays the taste and virtue
of the age weaken and attenuate the will, nothing is so adapted to the
spirit of the age as weakness of will consequently, in the ideal of the
philosopher, strength of will, sternness, and capacity for prolonged
resolution, must specially be included in the conception of "greatness",
with as good a right as the opposite doctrine, with its ideal of a silly,
renouncing, humble, selfless humanity, was suited to an opposite age—such
as the sixteenth century, which suffered from its accumulated energy of
will, and from the wildest torrents and floods of selfishness In the time
of Socrates, among men only of worn-out instincts, old conservative
Athenians who let themselves go—"for the sake of happiness," as they
said, for the sake of pleasure, as their conduct indicated—and who
had continually on their lips the old pompous words to which they had long
forfeited the right by the life they led, IRONY was perhaps necessary for
greatness of soul, the wicked Socratic assurance of the old physician and
plebeian, who cut ruthlessly into his own flesh, as into the flesh and
heart of the "noble," with a look that said plainly enough "Do not
dissemble before me! here—we are equal!" At present, on the
contrary, when throughout Europe the herding-animal alone attains to
honours, and dispenses honours, when "equality of right" can too readily
be transformed into equality in wrong—I mean to say into general war
against everything rare, strange, and privileged, against the higher man,
the higher soul, the higher duty, the higher responsibility, the creative
plenipotence and lordliness—at present it belongs to the conception
of "greatness" to be noble, to wish to be apart, to be capable of being
different, to stand alone, to have to live by personal initiative, and the
philosopher will betray something of his own ideal when he asserts "He
shall be the greatest who can be the most solitary, the most concealed,
the most divergent, the man beyond good and evil, the master of his
virtues, and of super-abundance of will; precisely this shall be called
GREATNESS: as diversified as can be entire, as ample as can be full." And
to ask once more the question: Is greatness POSSIBLE—nowadays?</p>
<p>213. It is difficult to learn what a philosopher is, because it cannot be
taught: one must "know" it by experience—or one should have the
pride NOT to know it. The fact that at present people all talk of things
of which they CANNOT have any experience, is true more especially and
unfortunately as concerns the philosopher and philosophical matters:—the
very few know them, are permitted to know them, and all popular ideas
about them are false. Thus, for instance, the truly philosophical
combination of a bold, exuberant spirituality which runs at presto pace,
and a dialectic rigour and necessity which makes no false step, is unknown
to most thinkers and scholars from their own experience, and therefore,
should any one speak of it in their presence, it is incredible to them.
They conceive of every necessity as troublesome, as a painful compulsory
obedience and state of constraint; thinking itself is regarded by them as
something slow and hesitating, almost as a trouble, and often enough as
"worthy of the SWEAT of the noble"—but not at all as something easy
and divine, closely related to dancing and exuberance! "To think" and to
take a matter "seriously," "arduously"—that is one and the same
thing to them; such only has been their "experience."—Artists have
here perhaps a finer intuition; they who know only too well that precisely
when they no longer do anything "arbitrarily," and everything of
necessity, their feeling of freedom, of subtlety, of power, of creatively
fixing, disposing, and shaping, reaches its climax—in short, that
necessity and "freedom of will" are then the same thing with them. There
is, in fine, a gradation of rank in psychical states, to which the
gradation of rank in the problems corresponds; and the highest problems
repel ruthlessly every one who ventures too near them, without being
predestined for their solution by the loftiness and power of his
spirituality. Of what use is it for nimble, everyday intellects, or
clumsy, honest mechanics and empiricists to press, in their plebeian
ambition, close to such problems, and as it were into this "holy of
holies"—as so often happens nowadays! But coarse feet must never
tread upon such carpets: this is provided for in the primary law of
things; the doors remain closed to those intruders, though they may dash
and break their heads thereon. People have always to be born to a high
station, or, more definitely, they have to be BRED for it: a person has
only a right to philosophy—taking the word in its higher
significance—in virtue of his descent; the ancestors, the "blood,"
decide here also. Many generations must have prepared the way for the
coming of the philosopher; each of his virtues must have been separately
acquired, nurtured, transmitted, and embodied; not only the bold, easy,
delicate course and current of his thoughts, but above all the readiness
for great responsibilities, the majesty of ruling glance and contemning
look, the feeling of separation from the multitude with their duties and
virtues, the kindly patronage and defense of whatever is misunderstood and
calumniated, be it God or devil, the delight and practice of supreme
justice, the art of commanding, the amplitude of will, the lingering eye
which rarely admires, rarely looks up, rarely loves....</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />