<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0002" id="link2HCH0002"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER II. THE EXISTENCE OF MATTER </h2>
<p>In this chapter we have to ask ourselves whether, in any sense at all,
there is such a thing as matter. Is there a table which has a certain
intrinsic nature, and continues to exist when I am not looking, or is the
table merely a product of my imagination, a dream-table in a very
prolonged dream? This question is of the greatest importance. For if we
cannot be sure of the independent existence of objects, we cannot be sure
of the independent existence of other people's bodies, and therefore still
less of other people's minds, since we have no grounds for believing in
their minds except such as are derived from observing their bodies. Thus
if we cannot be sure of the independent existence of objects, we shall be
left alone in a desert—it may be that the whole outer world is
nothing but a dream, and that we alone exist. This is an uncomfortable
possibility; but although it cannot be strictly proved to be false, there
is not the slightest reason to suppose that it is true. In this chapter we
have to see why this is the case.</p>
<p>Before we embark upon doubtful matters, let us try to find some more or
less fixed point from which to start. Although we are doubting the
physical existence of the table, we are not doubting the existence of the
sense-data which made us think there was a table; we are not doubting
that, while we look, a certain colour and shape appear to us, and while we
press, a certain sensation of hardness is experienced by us. All this,
which is psychological, we are not calling in question. In fact, whatever
else may be doubtful, some at least of our immediate experiences seem
absolutely certain.</p>
<p>Descartes (1596-1650), the founder of modern philosophy, invented a method
which may still be used with profit—the method of systematic doubt.
He determined that he would believe nothing which he did not see quite
clearly and distinctly to be true. Whatever he could bring himself to
doubt, he would doubt, until he saw reason for not doubting it. By
applying this method he gradually became convinced that the only existence
of which he could be <i>quite</i> certain was his own. He imagined a
deceitful demon, who presented unreal things to his senses in a perpetual
phantasmagoria; it might be very improbable that such a demon existed, but
still it was possible, and therefore doubt concerning things perceived by
the senses was possible.</p>
<p>But doubt concerning his own existence was not possible, for if he did not
exist, no demon could deceive him. If he doubted, he must exist; if he had
any experiences whatever, he must exist. Thus his own existence was an
absolute certainty to him. 'I think, therefore I am,' he said (<i>Cogito,
ergo sum</i>); and on the basis of this certainty he set to work to build
up again the world of knowledge which his doubt had laid in ruins. By
inventing the method of doubt, and by showing that subjective things are
the most certain, Descartes performed a great service to philosophy, and
one which makes him still useful to all students of the subject.</p>
<p>But some care is needed in using Descartes' argument. 'I think, therefore
I am' says rather more than is strictly certain. It might seem as though
we were quite sure of being the same person to-day as we were yesterday,
and this is no doubt true in some sense. But the real Self is as hard to
arrive at as the real table, and does not seem to have that absolute,
convincing certainty that belongs to particular experiences. When I look
at my table and see a certain brown colour, what is quite certain at once
is not '<i>I</i> am seeing a brown colour', but rather, 'a brown colour is
being seen'. This of course involves something (or somebody) which (or
who) sees the brown colour; but it does not of itself involve that more or
less permanent person whom we call 'I'. So far as immediate certainty
goes, it might be that the something which sees the brown colour is quite
momentary, and not the same as the something which has some different
experience the next moment.</p>
<p>Thus it is our particular thoughts and feelings that have primitive
certainty. And this applies to dreams and hallucinations as well as to
normal perceptions: when we dream or see a ghost, we certainly do have the
sensations we think we have, but for various reasons it is held that no
physical object corresponds to these sensations. Thus the certainty of our
knowledge of our own experiences does not have to be limited in any way to
allow for exceptional cases. Here, therefore, we have, for what it is
worth, a solid basis from which to begin our pursuit of knowledge.</p>
<p>The problem we have to consider is this: Granted that we are certain of
our own sense-data, have we any reason for regarding them as signs of the
existence of something else, which we can call the physical object? When
we have enumerated all the sense-data which we should naturally regard as
connected with the table, have we said all there is to say about the
table, or is there still something else—something not a sense-datum,
something which persists when we go out of the room? Common sense
unhesitatingly answers that there is. What can be bought and sold and
pushed about and have a cloth laid on it, and so on, cannot be a <i>mere</i>
collection of sense-data. If the cloth completely hides the table, we
shall derive no sense-data from the table, and therefore, if the table
were merely sense-data, it would have ceased to exist, and the cloth would
be suspended in empty air, resting, by a miracle, in the place where the
table formerly was. This seems plainly absurd; but whoever wishes to
become a philosopher must learn not to be frightened by absurdities.</p>
<p>One great reason why it is felt that we must secure a physical object in
addition to the sense-data, is that we want the same object for different
people. When ten people are sitting round a dinner-table, it seems
preposterous to maintain that they are not seeing the same tablecloth, the
same knives and forks and spoons and glasses. But the sense-data are
private to each separate person; what is immediately present to the sight
of one is not immediately present to the sight of another: they all see
things from slightly different points of view, and therefore see them
slightly differently. Thus, if there are to be public neutral objects,
which can be in some sense known to many different people, there must be
something over and above the private and particular sense-data which
appear to various people. What reason, then, have we for believing that
there are such public neutral objects?</p>
<p>The first answer that naturally occurs to one is that, although different
people may see the table slightly differently, still they all see more or
less similar things when they look at the table, and the variations in
what they see follow the laws of perspective and reflection of light, so
that it is easy to arrive at a permanent object underlying all the
different people's sense-data. I bought my table from the former occupant
of my room; I could not buy <i>his</i> sense-data, which died when he went
away, but I could and did buy the confident expectation of more or less
similar sense-data. Thus it is the fact that different people have similar
sense-data, and that one person in a given place at different times has
similar sense-data, which makes us suppose that over and above the
sense-data there is a permanent public object which underlies or causes
the sense-data of various people at various times.</p>
<p>Now in so far as the above considerations depend upon supposing that there
are other people besides ourselves, they beg the very question at issue.
Other people are represented to me by certain sense-data, such as the
sight of them or the sound of their voices, and if I had no reason to
believe that there were physical objects independent of my sense-data, I
should have no reason to believe that other people exist except as part of
my dream. Thus, when we are trying to show that there must be objects
independent of our own sense-data, we cannot appeal to the testimony of
other people, since this testimony itself consists of sense-data, and does
not reveal other people's experiences unless our own sense-data are signs
of things existing independently of us. We must therefore, if possible,
find, in our own purely private experiences, characteristics which show,
or tend to show, that there are in the world things other than ourselves
and our private experiences.</p>
<p>In one sense it must be admitted that we can never prove the existence of
things other than ourselves and our experiences. No logical absurdity
results from the hypothesis that the world consists of myself and my
thoughts and feelings and sensations, and that everything else is mere
fancy. In dreams a very complicated world may seem to be present, and yet
on waking we find it was a delusion; that is to say, we find that the
sense-data in the dream do not appear to have corresponded with such
physical objects as we should naturally infer from our sense-data. (It is
true that, when the physical world is assumed, it is possible to find
physical causes for the sense-data in dreams: a door banging, for
instance, may cause us to dream of a naval engagement. But although, in
this case, there is a physical cause for the sense-data, there is not a
physical object corresponding to the sense-data in the way in which an
actual naval battle would correspond.) There is no logical impossibility
in the supposition that the whole of life is a dream, in which we
ourselves create all the objects that come before us. But although this is
not logically impossible, there is no reason whatever to suppose that it
is true; and it is, in fact, a less simple hypothesis, viewed as a means
of accounting for the facts of our own life, than the common-sense
hypothesis that there really are objects independent of us, whose action
on us causes our sensations.</p>
<p>The way in which simplicity comes in from supposing that there really are
physical objects is easily seen. If the cat appears at one moment in one
part of the room, and at another in another part, it is natural to suppose
that it has moved from the one to the other, passing over a series of
intermediate positions. But if it is merely a set of sense-data, it cannot
have ever been in any place where I did not see it; thus we shall have to
suppose that it did not exist at all while I was not looking, but suddenly
sprang into being in a new place. If the cat exists whether I see it or
not, we can understand from our own experience how it gets hungry between
one meal and the next; but if it does not exist when I am not seeing it,
it seems odd that appetite should grow during non-existence as fast as
during existence. And if the cat consists only of sense-data, it cannot be
hungry, since no hunger but my own can be a sense-datum to me. Thus the
behaviour of the sense-data which represent the cat to me, though it seems
quite natural when regarded as an expression of hunger, becomes utterly
inexplicable when regarded as mere movements and changes of patches of
colour, which are as incapable of hunger as a triangle is of playing
football.</p>
<p>But the difficulty in the case of the cat is nothing compared to the
difficulty in the case of human beings. When human beings speak—that
is, when we hear certain noises which we associate with ideas, and
simultaneously see certain motions of lips and expressions of face—it
is very difficult to suppose that what we hear is not the expression of a
thought, as we know it would be if we emitted the same sounds. Of course
similar things happen in dreams, where we are mistaken as to the existence
of other people. But dreams are more or less suggested by what we call
waking life, and are capable of being more or less accounted for on
scientific principles if we assume that there really is a physical world.
Thus every principle of simplicity urges us to adopt the natural view,
that there really are objects other than ourselves and our sense-data
which have an existence not dependent upon our perceiving them.</p>
<p>Of course it is not by argument that we originally come by our belief in
an independent external world. We find this belief ready in ourselves as
soon as we begin to reflect: it is what may be called an <i>instinctive</i>
belief. We should never have been led to question this belief but for the
fact that, at any rate in the case of sight, it seems as if the
sense-datum itself were instinctively believed to be the independent
object, whereas argument shows that the object cannot be identical with
the sense-datum. This discovery, however—which is not at all
paradoxical in the case of taste and smell and sound, and only slightly so
in the case of touch—leaves undiminished our instinctive belief that
there <i>are</i> objects <i>corresponding</i> to our sense-data. Since
this belief does not lead to any difficulties, but on the contrary tends
to simplify and systematize our account of our experiences, there seems no
good reason for rejecting it. We may therefore admit—though with a
slight doubt derived from dreams—that the external world does really
exist, and is not wholly dependent for its existence upon our continuing
to perceive it.</p>
<p>The argument which has led us to this conclusion is doubtless less strong
than we could wish, but it is typical of many philosophical arguments, and
it is therefore worth while to consider briefly its general character and
validity. All knowledge, we find, must be built up upon our instinctive
beliefs, and if these are rejected, nothing is left. But among our
instinctive beliefs some are much stronger than others, while many have,
by habit and association, become entangled with other beliefs, not really
instinctive, but falsely supposed to be part of what is believed
instinctively.</p>
<p>Philosophy should show us the hierarchy of our instinctive beliefs,
beginning with those we hold most strongly, and presenting each as much
isolated and as free from irrelevant additions as possible. It should take
care to show that, in the form in which they are finally set forth, our
instinctive beliefs do not clash, but form a harmonious system. There can
never be any reason for rejecting one instinctive belief except that it
clashes with others; thus, if they are found to harmonize, the whole
system becomes worthy of acceptance.</p>
<p>It is of course <i>possible</i> that all or any of our beliefs may be
mistaken, and therefore all ought to be held with at least some slight
element of doubt. But we cannot have <i>reason</i> to reject a belief
except on the ground of some other belief. Hence, by organizing our
instinctive beliefs and their consequences, by considering which among
them is most possible, if necessary, to modify or abandon, we can arrive,
on the basis of accepting as our sole data what we instinctively believe,
at an orderly systematic organization of our knowledge, in which, though
the <i>possibility</i> of error remains, its likelihood is diminished by
the interrelation of the parts and by the critical scrutiny which has
preceded acquiescence.</p>
<p>This function, at least, philosophy can perform. Most philosophers,
rightly or wrongly, believe that philosophy can do much more than this—that
it can give us knowledge, not otherwise attainable, concerning the
universe as a whole, and concerning the nature of ultimate reality.
Whether this be the case or not, the more modest function we have spoken
of can certainly be performed by philosophy, and certainly suffices, for
those who have once begun to doubt the adequacy of common sense, to
justify the arduous and difficult labours that philosophical problems
involve.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />