<h2><SPAN name="CHAPTER_IV" id="CHAPTER_IV">CHAPTER IV</SPAN></h2>
<p class="center">MENTAL POWERS OF SPIDERS</p>
<p><span class="smcap">Before</span> leaving the garden-spider let us undertake
some little investigation of its mental powers—if it
possesses any. The commonest mistake with regard
to all animals is to interpret their actions from the
human standpoint, and to credit them with emotions
and with deliberate forethought of which there is in<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_21" id="Page_21">[Pg 21]</SPAN></span>
reality no proof whatever. The power to spin such a
complicated snare as we have just described predisposes
us to attribute a high order of intelligence to
a creature capable of such an achievement, and when
it “shams death” on being disturbed we immediately
pronounce it “cunning.” The wildest conclusions
are sometimes arrived at. One author, for instance,
states that he has seen an Attid spider “instructing
its young ones how to hunt” and adds that “whenever
an old one missed its leap, it would run from the
place and hide itself in some crevice as if ashamed of
its mismanagement.” Such inferences, of course, were
entirely unwarranted from the facts observed. Now
the fact that a newly-hatched garden-spider can make
a complete snare without ever having seen the operation
performed immediately relegates that action
to the realm of instinct,—not less wonderful than
intelligence perhaps, but certainly quite distinct from
it. With the much discussed origin of instinct we
are not here concerned, but a pure instinct differs
from intelligence in this: that it is due to inherited
nervous mechanism and results in actions the object
of which may be quite unknown to the actors.
There is no conscious adaptation of means to an end.
When a young spider spins a web there is not only
no evidence that it does so with the deliberate purpose
of catching flies, but many known facts go to
prove that it performs the feat, “because it feels as<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_22" id="Page_22">[Pg 22]</SPAN></span>
if it must,” and is quite ignorant of the purpose to be
subserved.</p>
<p>It is no doubt quite beyond our power to ascertain
accurately the mental condition of a spider, but it is
perfectly easy to make a few illuminating experiments
on two points which have a very decided bearing on
intelligence:—the development of the senses, and the
degree of what has been called <i>educability</i>, or the
power of learning from experience. To what extent can
the spider see, hear, smell, feel, taste? How far is it
capable of varying its action as the result of experience?
The senses, as far as we know, are the
principal—if not the only—avenues by which external
impressions can reach the seat of intelligence, and
there is no surer indication of the intelligence of an
animal than the degree to which it is susceptible of
education. Probably most readers know the immortal
story of the pike cited by Darwin in the <i>Descent
of Man</i>. The pike was in an aquarium, separated by
a sheet of glass from a tank in which were numerous
small fish. Not till three months had expired
did the pike cease to dash itself against the glass
partition in its attempts to seize the fish in the neighbouring
tank. It then desisted and had evidently
learnt something—but what? After three months,
the glass partition was removed, but the pike refused
to attack those particular fish, though it immediately
seized any new specimens introduced to the tank. All<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_23" id="Page_23">[Pg 23]</SPAN></span>
that it had apparently learnt was that an attack on a
particular fish resulted in a violent blow on the nose.
Some degree of intelligence must be conceded to the
pike, but it can hardly be considered of a high
order.</p>
<p>Now the garden-spider possesses eight eyes, and
might be expected to see fairly well, but the experimenter
will very soon come to the conclusion that
the habitual use it makes of them—at all events in
day-light—is very slight. Touch a web with a vibrating
tuning-fork and the spider will rush to the spot
and investigate the instrument with its fore-legs
before distinguishing it from a fly. Remember, however,
that this is only true of what are sometimes
called sedentary spiders; species which hunt their
prey have much better vision. Yet even among
sedentary spiders the power of sight is not negligible,
for a most trustworthy observer states that he has
several times seen <i>Meta segmentata</i>, a very common
small Epeirid, drop from its web to secure an insect
on the ground beneath, and return with it by way of
the drop line, and the same action has been observed
in the case of <i>Theridion</i>, which spins an irregular
snare.</p>
<p>There are peculiar difficulties attending experiments
on the subject of hearing. An absolutely deaf
person may be aware of the sounding of a deep organ
note through the sense of feeling, and a well-known<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_24" id="Page_24">[Pg 24]</SPAN></span>
experimenter was on the point of drawing interesting
conclusions from the behaviour of a spider in response
to the notes of a flute, when he found that precisely
the same results were obtained by a soundless puff of
air. It seems hardly possible to make sure, in the
case of a spider in a snare, that the sound vibrations
are not <i>felt</i>, apart from any sense of hearing, and it
is a remarkable fact that it is only the snare-spinning
spiders that make any response to sounds:—free-roving
spiders are apparently quite deaf.</p>
<p>In experimenting with sound we must take two
precautions: the instrument used must not necessitate
any marked action which may be visible to the
spider, nor must it give rise to palpable air-currents.
These requirements are best met by a tuning-fork of
not too low a pitch. We cannot <i>feel</i> the air vibrations
emanating from it, but can only perceive them
by the ear, but we have no proof that the spider’s
sense of touch ceases precisely at the same point as
our own. However, no better instrument for experiment
seems to be available, so we take a tuning-fork,
and approach it cautiously—in the quiescent state—towards
the spider, stationed, we will suppose, in the
centre of its snare. No notice is taken, and we carefully
withdraw it, set it vibrating, and approach it
again in the same manner. There is now generally
a response, the spider raising its front legs and
extending them in the direction of the fork, or, if the<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_25" id="Page_25">[Pg 25]</SPAN></span>
sound is loud, dropping suddenly by a thread and
remaining suspended some inches below the snare.
The experiment should be repeated several times
with the fork sometimes still, sometimes vibrating,
and the conclusion arrived at will be that the spider
is aware of the vibrating fork—but by which sense?
It is noteworthy that a fork giving a low note is
always most effective.</p>
<p>Now here is a very remarkable fact. In two
widely different groups of spiders—the Theraphosidae
or so called “bird-eating spiders” and the Theridiidae—there
are species with a stridulating or sound-making
apparatus, and we should hardly expect a deaf
creature to evolve an elaborate mechanism for the
production of sound. This is a matter, however, that
we shall discuss later.</p>
<p>No amount of research has succeeded in localising
the sense of hearing in spiders, supposing it to exist.
The creature may lose any of its five pairs of limbs
(four pairs of legs and one pair of pedipalps) without
alteration in its response to sound. If the front legs
are missing the second pair are raised when the vibrating
fork is approached.</p>
<p>It is fairly easy to test the sense of smell in these
creatures, the only necessary precaution being that
no acid or pungent substances capable of having an
irritating effect on the skin, such as vinegar or
ammonia, must be employed. Such perfumes as<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_26" id="Page_26">[Pg 26]</SPAN></span>
lavender or heliotrope are free from this defect.
Take a clean glass rod and present it to the spider
as before, and no notice is taken. Now dip it in oil
of lavender, allow it to dry, and present it again.
Most spiders respond to such a test, Epeirids generally
raising the abdomen, and rubbing one or other
of the legs against the jaws, while jumping spiders
generally raise the head and back away from the rod.
Different essences produce different effects, but there
is seldom any doubt that the creature is aware of
their presence; it is not deficient in the sense of
smell, but its localisation has hitherto baffled research.</p>
<p>The sense of taste does not seem to have been
made the subject of any definite experiments among
spiders, though such experiments might well lead to
interesting conclusions, and the reader might do worse
than undertake some on his own account. It would
be easy, for instance, to supply a garden-spider with
various insects which are generally rejected by other
insectivorous animals, and to note its behaviour. It
might refuse to have anything to do with them, or it
might sample them and turn away in disgust. In the
first case the explanation might be that it was warned
of their probably evil taste by their coloration or
smell, but in any case here is an interesting little
field for research. It is the general belief among
arachnologists that the sense of taste is well developed
among spiders, and it is highly improbable<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_27" id="Page_27">[Pg 27]</SPAN></span>
that a sense so necessary for the discrimination of
suitable food should be lacking in animals with so
respectable a sensory equipment.</p>
<p>There is no doubt at all that the sense of touch
is extremely well developed in spiders, especially
perhaps, in the sedentary groups, and it is probable
that, under ordinary circumstances, the garden-spider
works almost entirely by its guidance. Whether in
the centre of the web or in its retreat under a neighbouring
leaf it is in direct communication with every
part of its snare by silken lines, and the least
disturbance usually suffices to bring it to the spot;
and then, as we have said, it will generally touch the
disturbing object, however unpromising in appearance,
before deciding on its line of action. There is little
doubt that many of the numerous hairs and bristles
with which its limbs are furnished are distinctly
sensory in function.</p>
<p>So much, then, as to the senses of spiders; but
what about their “educability”—their power of
learning from experience? Here is evidently a wide
subject, and a difficult one full of pit-falls for the
unwary, but we may nevertheless draw some inferences
from the quite elementary experiments on the senses
which have been outlined above. A spider drops on
account of the sounding of the tuning-fork in its
neighbourhood; can it be educated to take no notice
of the sound after repeatedly finding that no evil<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_28" id="Page_28">[Pg 28]</SPAN></span>
consequences follow? It will perhaps be most instructive
to give in a condensed form the results
of an actual experiment selected from many performed
by two American arachnologists, George and
Elizabeth Peckham, whose researches have thrown
more light than any others upon the mental equipment
of spiders. They had an individual of the
small Epeirid species <i>Cyclosa conica</i> under observation
for a month, and tested it almost daily
with the tuning-fork. At the sound of the fork the
spider would drop; when it had recovered itself and
returned to the snare the fork would be sounded again,
and so on. Now on July 20 the spider fell nine times
successively—the last three times only an inch or
two—and then took no further notice of the vibrating
fork. On subsequent days, until August 5, she fell
either five, six or seven times, except on two occasions
when a day’s test had been omitted, and then eleven
successive falls occurred before the spider ceased to
respond. On August 5 she seemed startled at the
sound but did not fall, though the fork was sounded
nine times. During the remainder of the experiment
she generally remained perfectly indifferent to the
fork, though on one or two occasions she partially
forgot her lesson and dropped a very short distance,
immediately recovering herself.</p>
<p>Observe that the basis of educability is memory.
For a fortnight, in the case of this particular spider,<span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_29" id="Page_29">[Pg 29]</SPAN></span>
the lesson learnt on one day seemed to be entirely
forgotten the next morning, but thereafter a definite
change of habit seemed to result. This does not
appear a very great intellectual achievement, but it
is by no means despicable, for it must be borne in
mind that the habit of dropping when alarmed is
almost the only means of defence such a spider
possesses, and the instinct which prompts it must be
very strongly ingrained. In the words of the experimenters—“Taking
this into consideration, it seems
remarkable that one of them should so soon have
learned the sound of the vibrating fork, and should
have modified her action accordingly.”</p>
<p>This single experiment has been here described in
some detail largely for the purpose of impressing the
reader with the importance of reducing the problem
to its simplest terms before any inferences are drawn,
and it may well act as a model for any which he may
be inclined to undertake on his own account. The
more complicated the action, the more likely is the
experimenter to read into it motives and mental
operations which exist only in his own imagination,
and with this warning we must take leave of a subject
which might tempt us to encroach too much on an
allotted space.</p>
<hr class="chap" />
<p><span class="pagenum"><SPAN name="Page_30" id="Page_30">[Pg 30]</SPAN></span></p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />